A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

download A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

of 7

Transcript of A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    1/7

     

    This essay argues that Anderson’s

    definition of the nation as a community

    that is imagined, limited and sovereign,

    while correctly identifying nations as

    constructed, is insufficient. In fact,Anderson fails to give a definition at all, by

    not explaining how the nation is distinct

    from other ‘styles’ of community.

    Consequently, his community could be

    imagined in premodern times.

    A critique of

    Benedict

    Anderson’s

    “ImaginedCommunities” 

    Konstantin Sietzy

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    2/7

    2

    Introduction

    When Benedict Anderson’s Imagined Communities was published in 1983, it arrived right in the middle

    of a large, and largely one-sided series of texts purporting modernist origins of nationalism. Neither

    was Anderson the first to regard nationalism and nations as constructed, as he himself acknowledges

    (Anderson, 2006: xii),1 nor is Imagined Communities still very present in contemporary modernist

    writing on the subject, except as an obligatory cursory reference (cf. e.g. chapter one in Hutchinson

    and Smith, 1994; Breuilly, 2006: xliv). Nevertheless, Anderson’s phrase of the imagined community

    has remained resonant inside and even outside of the academic study of nationalism for over four

    decades.

    Thus it is more than surprising that upon careful consideration Anderson does not give an

    operational definition of the nation at all. Anderson fails to define the nation as a discrete entity by

    failing to describe how it is distinct from other ‘styles’ of community (Anderson’s term).   In

    consequence, imaging a community in Anderson’s sense is by no means possible only in modern times;

    this can be illustrated by showing that his criteria apply without alteration to, for example, a medieval

    city.

    The Nation as an Imagined Community

    Anderson’s classic definition of the nation as an imagined community is analytically convincing and

    empirically observable: “the members of even the smallest nation will never know most of their

    fellow-members, meet them, or even hear of them, yet in the minds of each lives the image of their

    communion" (Anderson, 2006: 6). It is also minimalist. In fact, ‘imagined’ can be stretched to denote

    the simple fact that the nation is a constructed idea, not (necessarily) rooted in empirically observable

    qualities. Requiring the empirical-historical existence of such primordial qualities (as opposed to a

    belief  that they exist!) is largely discarded in contemporary literature on the subject. Two processes in

    which the modern nation works as an imagined (in the sense of constructed) community relate to

    collective  forgetting: forgetting the very fact that the common past is invented, and forgetting that

    nationalism itself exists, as a precondition for nationalist sentiments diffusing through every aspect of

    society and culture.

    Why would the nation not be imagined? As far back as Joseph Stalin, observers have pointed

    out that “a common language is one of the characteristic features of a nation.” (Stalin, 1994: 19;

    emphasis in the original). Van den Berghe (1994: 96-97) presents “a socio-biological perspective”

    1 Steven T. Engel points out correctly that “the fundamental insight that nations were founded on imagination

    was recognized by Rousseau 200 years before Anderson” (Engel, 2005: 537).

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    3/7

    3

    when he proposes that “ethnic and race sentiments are to be understood as an extended and

    attenuated form of kin selection.” Yet the empirical validity of such primordial attachments is largely

    discounted by present-day scholars. Breuilly (2005: 32-33) claims that “ethnic myths or memories do

    not matter. People have plenty of other ways to provide collective identity .” Furthermore, Eller and

    Coughlan (1993) demonstrate that primordialists provide only unsatisfactory explanatory models.

    The folly of primordial ties is illustrated vividly by the twentieth-century history of the

    ‘Germanic’ states of Central and Western Europe. The core countries containing linguistically German

    populations, Austria, Switzerland, and the Federal Republic, have long developed into distinct

    communities that are both limited and sovereign. Despite this, ethno-linguistic ties (in the passive

    rather than active sense of the word) remain. Anyone claiming that Swiss-German is a distinct

    language rather than a dialect (Blocher, 2013) has never travelled to the alemannisch region of

    Southern Germany, comprising the strip of land between Rhine and Lake Constance, where a dialect

    almost identical to that on the other side of the Swiss-German border is spoken2 (and on top of this

    displays a distinct ignorance of the state-of-the-art of linguistics theory; cf. Glaser, 2013). As for

    Austrian, the differences are still more insignificant. Ethnically, that the question of a renewed

     Anschluss is not even part of Austrian public discourse is admirably demonstrated by the fact that a

    sweeping web search reveals not a single public opinion poll on this topic since at least the 1990s

    (converse to the above, Switzerland must not be mentioned here). 3 

    Given the recency of this development (in the Austrian case, historical consensus is that the

    1938 Anschluss referendum, polling 99.73%, required no ex post manipulation by the authorities; cf.

    Verein demokratische Bildung, 2003) it becomes clear that a central part of imagining is forgetting the

    very fact that the nation’s different groups’ common past is invented, or in Billig’s terms: “the nation,

    which celebrates its antiquity, forgets its historical recency” (Billig, 1995: 38). Secondly, but of at least

    the same importance, is a nation’s ability to forget its inherent nationalism itself. Relegating

    nationalism to the collective subconscious is a vital step on a nation’s path to maturity. Whereas in

    conflicted nations, open nationalism is an important tool of promoting social cohesion for elites,4 in

    established societies it is at most separatist, or extreme-right groups, that openly run on an explicitly

    nationalist platform. Governmental leaders, on the contrary, master the art of habitually evoking

    2 Interestingly, a major distinguishing character of the dialects is the common sporadic influence of French

    through pronunciation and gallicisms.3 The mass exodus of ‘ethnic Germans’ from Czechoslovakia, Poland and Hungary post-1945 provides no

    objection to this argument, but rather illustrates the instrumental nature of identity with regards to

    distinguishing between ‘us’ and ‘them’: prior to 1933 (and perhaps even 1939), these identities provided littlecause for friction.4 Cf. e.g. Gregorian (1967) on constructive nationalist discourse in the media in early 20th-century Afghanistan.

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    4/7

    4

    nationalistic sympathies, “daily reproduction” of the nation-state, in such a way that “this reminding

    is so familiar, so continual, that it is not consciously registered as reminding” (Billig, 1995: 6).To Billig,

    “the metonymic image of banal nationalism is not a flag which is being consciously waved with fervent

    passion; it is the flag hanging unnoticed on the public building” (Billig, 1995: 8).

    The Nation as a Distinct Style of Community

    Thus, in a sense, Anderson’s factor of the community being imagined is a necessary but, as indicated

    above, not a sufficient condition for it to present a nation. He is emphatic in pointing out that

    "communities are to be distinguished by … the style in which they are imagined” (Anderson, 2006: 6).

    Yet he does not actually explain how the nation is different in ‘style’ from other communities.

    Anderson posits the nation against the ‘dynastic realm’ as well as the ‘religious community’;

    but this is a historical argument, displaying the origins of nations, rather than an analytical one. One

    can imagine a variety of forms of governance unit other than the nation-state that satisfy Anderson’s

    conditions of being a community imagined as both limited and sovereign (and indeed in the sense that

    Anderson employs these terms; this criticism is not merely semantic!). One of these possible

    alternatives is the medieval European city.  5 

    Premodern Imagined Communities – The Medieval City

    European (and perhaps non-European) cities of the Middle Ages can be shown, at minimum in the

    abstract (but compatible with a plethora of historical examples), to befit Anderson’s four criteria for

    constituting a nation.

    They were:

    a. 

    imagined, because "in fact, all communities larger than primordial villages of face-to-face

    contact (and perhaps even those) are imagined," according to his own definition (Anderson,

    2006: 6);

    b. limited, because a medieval town, by definition, imagined itself as "coterminous with

    mankind" (again, Anderson's definition of "limited") less than a nation;

    c. sovereign, because it may equally "dream of being free"; in fact, multiple were (the Swiss

    city states of Geneva or Basle, for example, or the German Hansestädte); and even if under

    5 The choice of this particular time-period is arbitrary; any premodern example could work. Indeed, the

    academic avoidance of the question of nationality among Ancient Greek city states is instructive. Gellner(2006: 14) is the only one to make even a cursory reference to Greek city states, only to dismiss them in a

    single sentence.

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    5/7

    5

    a federal system, it may be highly contentious to assign the status of the (most) relevant

    "governance unit" to the federal government (cf. Hechter, 2000: 10);

    d. a community, because the existence of "deep, horizontal comradeship" is dubious at the

    least for modern nations themselves; under Anderson's qualification that it may exist

    "regardless of the actual inequality and exploitation that may prevail in each," (Anderson,

    2006: 7) it is possible just as much in a township; and similarly because Anderson joins in

    the standard academic conception6  of how this community is realised, namely, that

    "millions of people … willingly … die for such limited imaginings" – which of course may also

    be equally true for the medieval town (again, refer to the examples of the Swiss towns - e.g.

    the Second  Kappeler War of 1531, costing the lives of hundreds of citizens in defence of

    their cities; cf. Meyer, 1977).

    Thus, ‘imagining’ in Anderson’s sense is clearly possible in premodern times.

    At the same time, without falling into the trap of equating the "nation" with "nation-state", it

    can be safely claimed that the medieval city or village did not constitute a ‘nation’ in any conventional,

    modern usage.7 Anderson himself would presumably instinctively deny this usage when asked; in fact,

    he uses the two as distinct entities in multiple instances throughout the text (e.g. Anderson, 2006: 42).

    ConclusionAnderson’s concept of the nation as imagined proves to be a necessary but insufficient component of

    its profitable definitions. Nations are imagined because they construct a common identity bonding

    together a number of individuals far larger than the practical benefits of grouping together warrant

    (except, perhaps, in wartime). Primordial attachments are not a relevant criterion as empirical

    examples show. Furthermore, a crucial component of such imagining is an implicit agreement to

    forget, both the very constructedness of a nation’s collective history itself, and the artificiality of its

    constant ‘flagging’. 

    Yet nations form only one of a multiplicity of possible ‘imagined communities’, even if one

    remains close to all of Anderson’s own definitional criteria. As such, it is very possible to construct

    such an imagined community in premodern times, and historical examples supporting this view

    abound, for example amongst Europe’s medieval cities. 

    6 Cf. e.g. Billig (1995: 1).7 Gellner (1964: 152): "What are the political units for most of human history? Small tribal or village units; city

    states; feudal segments loosely associated with each other or higher authority; dynastic empires; the loosemoral communities of a shared religion. How often do these political units coincide with those of 'nations', i.e.

    linguistic and cultural boundaries? Seldom."

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    6/7

    6

    Ultimately, Anderson makes a valuable contribution through enriching the academic

    vocabulary by a catchy phrase (in a non-ironic way; this mere fact has helped to popularise Anderson’s

    book and thus open up the academic study of nationalism one further bit beyond the ivory tower),

    and through a certain extent through his novel ideas on print capitalism (Anderson, 2006: chapter 2).

    Yet the disproportion between, when Anderson is cited in contemporary debates, the focus on these

    two ideas and the almost complete ignorance of the remaining pages of Imagined Communities, gives

    testimony to the extent to which his ideas have been assimilated into the mainstream of modernist

    writing on the subject.

  • 8/17/2019 A Critique of Benedict Andersons Imagine

    7/7

    7

    BibliographyAnderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism.

    Revised Edition. London: Verso, 2006. 

    Berghe, Pierre van den. “A Socio-Biological Perspective.” Hutchinson, John and Anthony D. Smith.

    Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1994. 96-103.

    Billig, Michael. Banal Nationalism. London: SAGE Publications Ltd, 1995.

    Blocher, Silvia. “Unsere Sprache ist Schweizerdeutsch!” 2013. Silvia Blocher Website. 

    .

    Breuilly, John. “Dating the Nation: How Old Is an Nation?” Ichijo, Atsuko and Gordana Uzelac. When

    Is the Nation? Towards an Understanding of Theories of Nationalism. London: Routledge,

    2005. 15-39.

    Breuilly, John. “Introduction.” Gellner, Ernest. Nations and Nationalism. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006. xiii-

    Iiii.

    Eller, Jack D. and Reed M. Coughlan. “The Poverty of Primordialism: The Demystification of Ethnic

    Attachments.” Ethnic and Racial Studies (1993): 181-202.

    Engel, Steven T. “Rousseau and Imagined Communities.” The Review of Politics (2005): 515-537.

    Gellner, Ernest. Nations and Nationalism. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.

    —. Thought and Change. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1964.

    Glaser, Elvira. “Ist das Schweizerdeutsche eine eigene Sprache?” 24 Aug. 2013. Universität Zürich

    Website. .

    Gregorian, V. “Mahmud Tarzi and Saraj-ol-Akhbar, Ideology of Nationalism and Modernization in

    Afghanistan.” Middle East Journal  (1967): 345 -368.

    Hechter, Michael. Containing Nationalism. New York: Oxford UP, 2000.

    Meyer, Helmut. “Krisenmanagement in Zürich nach dem Zweiten Kappeler Krieg.” Zwingliana (1977):

    349-369.

    Stalin, Joseph. “The Nation.” Hutchinson, John and Anthony D. Smith. Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford

    UP, 1994. 18-21.

    Verein demokratische Bildung. “Anschlussbegeisterung und Volksabstimmung.” 10 Oct. 2003.

    Nationalsozialismus.at. 10 Nov. 2013.

    .