28_Lachman

download 28_Lachman

of 18

Transcript of 28_Lachman

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    1/18

    ICNE YALE #28

    Moral Courage: Bridging Nursing Ethics and Patient SafetyVicki D. Lachman, PhD, APRN, MBE

    You gain strength, courage, and confidence by every experience in

    which you really stop to look fear in the face. You are able to say, "I

    lived through this horror. I can take the next thing that comes

    along." . . . You must do the thing you think you cannot do.

    Eleanor Roosevelt

    The seriousness of the problem of patient safety has been widely documented since the

    Institute of Medicine (IOM) 1999 landmark report, To Err is Human (Blendon, et al.,

    2002; Healey, Shackford, Osler, Rogers & Burns, 2002; Starfield, 2000).

    Since most errors fall within the sphere of nursing practice, administrators, physicians

    and nurses see patient safety predominantly as a nursing responsibility (Cook, Hoas,

    Guttmannova, & Joyner, 2004). To bridge the gap that presently exists in patient safety

    initiatives, nurses must demonstrate moral courage. We have an ethical obligation to our

    patients to do everything we can logically do to make sure they are safe. First, do no

    harm. An immense challenge lies before us, but for our patients sake we must meet this

    ethical test with moral courage.

    This paper with begin with a historical overview of the concept of moral courage from

    Aristotle to a present day definition in the book by Kidder (2005). Ethical obligations will

    also be extracted from the Code of Ethics for Nurses (2001) to illustrate nursings

    responsibility in preventing and disclosing, as well as policy development in patient

    safety imperative. Five strategies to comply with this ethical imperative for patient safety

    will also be outlined.

    1

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    2/18

    Historical overview of the concept of moral courage

    The early writings of Aristotle were focused on the courage required in war. The

    dismantling of the Athenian Empire was occurring due to the Peloponnesian War. In

    Nicomachean Ethics (NE), Aristotles (1954) discussion of courage centers on the

    battlefield; dying in battle was considered noble, unlike dying from disease. Aristotles

    view of courage differed from his teacher Plato. According to Plato, courage is one of

    the four cardinal virtues in the lasting tradition of moral character (Stanford Encyclopedia

    of Philosophy, 2007). The other three qualities are temperance, justice and wisdom.

    However, Aristotles focus was not on cardinal virtues, but on two types of virtues:

    virtue of thought and virtue of character (Aristotle, 1954). The former was improved

    through education and the latter was amplified through habit. Will is the result of the

    education in physical, mental and spiritual realms. Will is an executive function between

    impulses (appetites) and rational aspects of human experience. Socrates and Plato both

    thought that management of mind over body was the only way in which human actions

    could become good. Aristotle thought that action of habit was also necessary.

    Aristotle believed that virtue of courage was the balance (mean) between extremes of

    cowardice and rashness. Therefore, an individual might charge ahead into danger either

    because he is blinded by rage (terrorist) or because he is unaware (intoxication) to the

    dangers that lie ahead. According to Aristotle, courage is defined as having rational

    control of emotion and passion; the person is expected to have control over fear and other

    emotional states. In his view, people acted rationally despite their fears, not because they

    2

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    3/18

    did not experience fear. He thought that both deficient and excess in a virtue could be

    disastrous. Aristotle wrote he is courageous who endures and fears the right things, for

    the right motive, in the right manner, and at the right time and who displays confidence in

    a similar way (NE III7.1115b15-20).

    Aristotle was steadfast in his belief that a virtue, like courage, only be used for honorable

    ends. Plato argued that courage for wicked ends was a lack of the cardinal virtue of

    wisdom (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2007). Aristotles focal point was on

    importance of acting, not just the reasoning. He said that one must not only know what

    to do, but he must also be able to act accordingly (NE VII 1152a5-10).

    Socrates, Plato and Aristotle, upon who we base our philosophical considerations, did not

    live in our time of rampaging medical litigation. Disclosing a medical error, particularly

    when the nurse feels personally to blame, requires the virtue of moral courage. For

    justice to prevail in any situation, both human beings involved must have their interests

    considered, according to societal mores or laws (Mavroudis, Mavoudis, Naunheim, &

    Sade, 2005). The nurse must treat the patient in the same manner that s/he would want to

    be treated.

    Humility is also a virtue and a crucial one in responding to errors. By being humble,

    one has the capability for candidness to admit ones own imperfection. Through humility

    we know our personal limitations. Humility is defined as the awareness of and being at

    ease with ones imperfections (Crigger, 2004). By recognizing our own fallibility, we

    have a more sympathetic attitude toward others and more readiness to forgive ourselves

    3

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    4/18

    and others. Consequently, the ethical response to making a mistake begins with being

    humble enough to honestly disclose the error.

    This is supported by Kants moral theory of the categorical imperative against lying

    (Kant, 1996). This imperative states Act only on the maximum through which you can,

    at the same time, will that it become a universal law of values. According to Kant,

    anything less than full disclosure of the error would deny the patient his moral dignity.

    Trust between the patient and the nurse necessitates this open communication. Nurses are

    obligated to steer clear of intentional deception (e.g. stating that the injury occurred

    because of other believable causes).

    If we fast forward to today, authors tend to see the virtue of moral courage as driven by

    principle (Kidder, 2005; Lachman, 2007). When courage supports our values and

    maintains core principles, we lean to using the term moral courage. Moral courage is

    about facing mental or social challenges that could wreck your reputation and emotional

    well-being, your adherence to conscience, and/or your self-esteem. The risks in acts of

    moral courage are humiliation, ridicule, unemployment and loss of social standing. The

    morally courageous person often goes against the grain, acting contrary to the accepted

    norm. Simply put, moral courage is the courage to be moral which means adhering to

    the five core moral values of honesty, respect, responsibility, fairness, and compassion

    (Kidder, 2005, p.10).

    Moral courage, like physical courage, requires the individual to overcome fear and stand

    up for his or her core values. It is the willingness to speak out and do what is right in the

    face of forces that would lead a person to act some other way (Lachman, 2007). Both

    Kidder and Lachman agree with Aristotle, moral courage is measured in action. It

    4

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    5/18

    requires a conscious reasoning of the risks and a willingness to act regardless of the risks.

    We have the ethical responsibility to determine what is needed for patient safety and to

    implement the training, mechanisms and strategies necessary (Sharpe, 2003).

    Patient safety initiative

    The IOM (1999) defines error as a the failure of a planned action to be completed as

    intended or the use of a wrong plan to achieve an aim. This could be an act of omission

    (e.g. not implementing appropriate antibiotic prophylaxis in pre-operative patient) or an

    act of commission (e.g. not decontaminating hands prior to and after direct contact with

    patient). The IOM called for an extensive national endeavor to redesign health care

    systems to make them safer and to develop a non-punitive attitude to errors.

    Instead of blaming and punishing individuals who make errors, the new approach is to

    examine and change faulty systems. A systems approach to preventing medical errors

    holds that systems set up individuals to make mistakes by faulty design of processes,

    problematic work conditions (e.g. disruptive physicians, untenable workloads etc.), lack

    of leadership supporting a culture of safety, flawed equipment design and maintenance

    and other factors (Reason, 1990). A systems approach increases reporting and actually

    empowers healthcare providers to contribute to systems improvement.

    Healthcare is a very complex, but other industries that are equally complex have better

    safety records. Examples include chemical manufacturing, nuclear power, and aviation.

    Leaders in these industries are recognized as high reliability organizations (HRO)

    because they manage for safe performance. The results of the research conducted on

    5

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    6/18

    these organizations will be included in the five strategies to bridge the gap to safety (The

    Institute for Safe Medication Practices (ISMP), 2005a). The first and the most critical

    underlying attribute of their accomplishments is a strong safety culture.

    Creating this culture of safety is the first strategy that will be discussed. The other

    strategies that will be described are implement and follow safe practices; create a

    reporting system that honors confidentiality; disclose the error and apologize; and deal

    with the problem nurses who are unable or unwilling to follow patient safety initiatives.

    Creating a culture of safety

    Culture is defined as a set of shared basic assumptions about the organizations values

    (what is important), beliefs (how things work), and behaviors (the way we do things) that

    have been reinforced in the workplace in an explicit or implicit ways (Senge et al., 1999).

    These assumptions have worked well enough to be considered valid and therefore, are

    taught to new members as the correct way to perceive, think, and feel in relation to

    problems. Culture is deeply rooted in an organizations history and collective experience.

    This strategic emphasis on safety by HROs is logically based on a healthy respect for the

    high-risk nature of the business and an obsession with the possibility for failure (ISMP,

    2005a). They know safety does not assure quality, but it is a requirement for high-quality

    service. But they are not driven by financial cost of errors; they are driven by the values

    that honor their commitment to society. This is the same ethical commitment we need in

    order to honor our patients.

    6

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    7/18

    This commitment begins at the top, but without a consistent message from managers that

    safety is a top priority the message will not be believable. These leaders and the

    workforce support an uncompromising intolerance for intentional risk-taking that could

    lead to error. Misconduct, such as refusal to do correct site verification, is an example of

    intentional risk-taking. In a safety culture the workforce trusts the leaders and each other

    to report and deal fairly with errors without retribution, concerns about safety are

    appreciated and rewarded. Near misses are seen as great catches and errors are

    opportunities to learn.

    Unfortunately, many healthcare organizations lack these characteristics of HRO culture

    of safety. Therefore, nurses need to understand their moral obligations and have the

    moral courage to do the right thing, regardless of the culture. A culture of safety supports

    nurses in preventing and reporting errors, but the accountability for patient safety never

    leaves the nursing professional.

    The American Nurses Association (2001) Code explicitly and implicitly states the nurses

    duty to patient safety; there are multiple statements that indicate the nurses moral

    obligation to prevent, report and disclose errors. Specifically, provision three in the Code

    states the nurse promotes, advocates for and strives to protect the health, safety and

    rights of the patient (ANA, 2001, p. 12). In provision six of the Code the nurse is

    informed of his or her responsibility for creating a moral environment. For example,

    acquiescing and accepting unsafe or inappropriate practices is equivalent to

    condoning unsafe practice (ANA, 2001, p.21). Silence must be broken if patient safety

    7

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    8/18

    is truly seen as an ethical imperative. It is in this provision that the specific mention of

    courage as a habit of a morally good person is revealed.

    Implement and follow safe practice

    The second strategy is to utilize what the research tells us will make the most difference

    in eliminating errors and avoidable adverse events. If the data is unambiguous, then the

    only morally legitimate action is 100% compliance. Therefore, it is imperative is to

    implement and follow the safe practices summarized by the National Quality Forum

    (2003). However, this list of 30 practices is not carried out in all hospitals; most have

    merely put into practice those mandated by Joint Commission on Accreditation of

    Healthcare Organizations (JCAHO) (2001).

    HROs carefully consider human factors such as sources of distraction, excessive

    workloads, unsafe staffing ratios etc (ISMP, 2005b). Nurses report that the

    majority of errors are caused by job overload, therefore, nurse staffing plays a

    major role in preventing errors (ANA, 2000). But we can not rely on education

    only to support these patient safety initiatives; technology such as bar coding

    patient identification and Pxyis medication administration can prevent errors.

    Nurses need to use other proven principles of error reduction such as

    standardization (e.g. time-out before surgical incision) and failsafes (e.g.

    medication can not be ordered from pharmacy before specific lab test is

    completed).The Code (2001) provision three speaks to the nurses ethical

    responsibility

    8

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    9/18

    to implement and maintain standards of professional nursing practice

    Nurses should also be active participants in the development of polices

    and review mechanisms designed to promote patient safety, reduce

    likelihood of errors, and address both environmental system factors and

    human factors that present increased risk to patients. (p. 13-14).

    This provision states it is not only the ethical obligation of the nurses to follow existing

    safe practices, but also the obligation to identify and address sources of error.

    Moral courage could be required in speaking up about any one of these 30 practices. For

    example, there is recognized safe practice for verbal orders- write down the order and

    read back to the prescriber. If a physician refuses to listen to the read back, then the nurse

    has to decide whether it is safe to give the medication. If the nurse does decide to give the

    medication, HROs would call this intentional risk-taking. Why would a nurse take this

    risk?

    In a 2003 survey on workplace intimidation, 40% of the respondents stated they had

    questions about the safety of an order in the past year but chose to take for granted the

    order was correct rather than talk with a prescriber they perceived as intimidating (ISMP,

    2004). A nurse needs to persist despite opposition; a helpful communication strategy such

    as SBAR(Situation-Background-Assessment-Recommendation) could help in the

    conflict resolution (Safer Healthcare). It is always easier to speak up in conflict when you

    have a model to frame the discussion.

    Create a reporting system that honors nurses confidentiality

    9

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    10/18

    The third strategy is establishing an effective reporting system. We have an ethical

    obligation to not only our patients, but to future patients. This is only done in a no

    blame culture where near misses are mined to prevent hazards to future patients. IOM

    (1999) recommends voluntary, confidential reporting systems within all healthcare

    institutions.

    The Code (2001) requires nurses to report errors to the appropriate supervisory personnel

    (p. 14). Under no circumstances should nurses attempt to hide an error; the focus must

    clearly be on correcting the error. If a punitive reporting system is in place, the nurse

    must still report error, but also work to change the system to one that focuses on

    improvement of patient safety. Provision six in the Code suggests nurses should not stay

    employed in organizations that habitually violate patient rights or who ask the nurse to

    compromise standards of practice (p. 21). Sometimes it takes more moral courage to

    leave than to stay in an environment that repeatedly puts patient safety and personal

    morality at risk.

    Disclose the error and apologize to the patient

    Disclosing the error is the fourth strategy to act ethically in patient safety. The injured

    patient has a right to know what happened (Leape, 2005). Yet, Cook et al. (2004)

    confirmed in one sub-study that only 64% would reveal the error to the patient affected,

    notwithstanding there was vast agreement between participants (97%) that an error had

    happened. The nurses role as a patient advocate requires disclosing the error, because

    10

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    11/18

    patients can not make appropriate decisions without the complete information. Such full

    disclosure supports patient autonomy (Kelley, 2002).

    JACHO standard R.I.1.2.2 requires that patients and when appropriate, their families,

    are informed about the outcome of care, including unanticipated outcomes. The standard

    is silent on scope and content of error disclosure (Banja, 2003). However, a qualitative

    study, which incorporated 45 nurses, determined six elements of disclosure that

    complement what patients desire. (Fein et al., 2007, p. 757).

    1. Admission: Did the discloser admit to the patient that there was an error?

    2. Discuss the event: Was the occurrence of the event containing the error clearly

    discussed with the patient?

    3. Link to proximate effect: Did the discloser communicate to the patient the link

    between the error and its proximate effect in a way the patient could understand?

    4. Proximate effect: Was the effect of the error discussed with the patient?

    5. Link to harm: If there was harm from the error, was the link between the error and

    harm sustained by the patient communicated in comprehensible fashion?

    6. Harm: If there was harm from the error, was there communication concerning the

    harm?

    The following example is a full disclosure using all six elements:

    Because of an error on my part, you got your insulin when you should not have.

    I apologize for that. It caused you to have very low blood sugar, which caused

    you to have a seizure. The seizure caused you to fall out of bed and that is when

    you broke your hip.

    11

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    12/18

    If the hospital also eliminates from the patients bill any costs linked with the error, then

    the nurse can also include this to the apology. The patients should not have to bear

    expenses caused by mistakes. All of us want to know what went wrong, why and what

    will be done to prevent it from happening to someone else.

    Presently, the system of liability for medical harms makes meeting this responsibility

    for disclosure probable only through courage. Our current system dampens this level of

    honesty and openness between health care professionals and patients. Viewed from the

    point of view of utility (greatest good for the greatness number), the tort process is

    unproductive. However, some early results indicate that patients are less likely to sue if

    healthcare providers admit responsibility and apologize (Leape, 2006).

    Take responsibility as profession for problem nurses

    This fifth strategy requires the reporting of nurses who are commit unethical, unlawful or

    incompetent acts to the appropriate person. If we put aside the rare psychopathic nurses

    who engage in nurse assisted suicide, the majority of problem nurses impaired

    performance is due to drug and alcohol abuse (estimated to afflict 6% to 8%), mental

    illness (15% lifetime risk) or physical illness (unknown, but author estimates 5%, but

    probably increasing, given average age of aging baby boomers). (ANA, 1984; Kessler et.

    al., 2005). Even allowing for an overlap of categories, at any one time 28% of nurses are

    at risk of posing a threat to patient safety. This percentage does not include nurses who

    are allowed to continue to practice even though they are not competent in knowledge

    and/or skill.

    12

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    13/18

    Most organizations do not have a good quality system to recognize nurses who have

    drug/alcohol abuse or mental illness. Nurses with physical illnesses, such as diabetes,

    may as well have impaired performance. This breakdown in guaranteeing competent and

    safe practice of all nurses is a major weakness of our professions commitment to patient

    safety. To accomplish our ethical responsibility to care for the public and help our

    colleagues we need improved systems of identification, support and re-entry.

    The Code (2001) speaks directly to the nurses responsibility to address impaired

    practice. Nurses must be vigilant to protect the patient, the public and the profession

    from potential harm when a colleagues practice, in any setting, appears to be impaired

    (p. 15). It is equally clear that if impaired practice is not corrected by the organization,

    the nurse has an obligation to report to pertinent licensing body of that profession. As

    noted in the Code, such reporting may present significant risks to the nurse, but such risks

    do not abolish the obligation to address threats to patient safety. The need for moral

    courage is obvious in this language.

    Conclusion

    The concept of moral courage began in the historical writings of Aristotle and Plato.

    They continue today because the ability to feel fear and speak and take appropriate action

    for values, beliefs and ethical obligations remains relevant in todays healthcare

    environment. The ethical obligation to patient safety can be found in the Code (2001) in

    numerous provisions. The five strategies to bridge nursing ethics and patient safety are

    13

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    14/18

    (1) create a safety culture (2) implement and follow safe practices, (3) create a reporting

    system that honors confidentiality, (4) disclose the error and apologize, and (5) deal with

    the problem nurses, who are unable or unwilling to follow patient safety initiatives.

    Moral courage is the bridge between our nursing ethical obligations and the realization of

    patient safety.

    References

    American Nurses Association (ANA). (1984).Addictions and psychological dysfunctions

    in nursing: The professions response to the problem. Kansas City, MO: American

    Nurses Publishing.

    American Nurses Association. (2000). New ANA study provides more proof of link

    between RN staffing and quality patient care. Retrieved May 15, 2008, from

    http://nursingworld.org/MainMenuCategories/ThePracticeofProfessionalNursing/PatientS

    afetyQuality/RNStaffingandQualityPatientCare.aspx

    American Nurses Association. (2001). Code for ethics for nurses with

    interpretative statements, Silver Spring, MD: American Nurses Publishing.

    Aristotle. (1954).Nichomachean Ethics book III. Ross, D (Trans.) London, England:

    Oxford University Press.

    Banja, J.D. (2003). Disclosing medical error: How much to tell?Journal of Healthcare

    Risk Management, 23(1), 11-14.

    14

    http://nursingworld.org/MainMenuCategories/ThePracticeofProfessionalNursing/PatientSafetyQuality/RNStaffingandQualityPatientCare.aspxhttp://nursingworld.org/MainMenuCategories/ThePracticeofProfessionalNursing/PatientSafetyQuality/RNStaffingandQualityPatientCare.aspxhttp://nursingworld.org/MainMenuCategories/ThePracticeofProfessionalNursing/PatientSafetyQuality/RNStaffingandQualityPatientCare.aspxhttp://nursingworld.org/MainMenuCategories/ThePracticeofProfessionalNursing/PatientSafetyQuality/RNStaffingandQualityPatientCare.aspx
  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    15/18

    Blendon, J., DesRoches, M., Brodie, M., Benson, J.M., Rosen, A.B., & Schneider E, et

    al. (2002). Views of practicing physicians and the public on medical errors.New England

    Journal of Medicine, 347(24), 1933-1940.

    Cook, A.F., Hoas, H., Guttmannova, K., & Joyner, J.C. (2004). An error by any other

    name.American Journal of Nursing, 104(6), 32-44.

    Crigger, N.J. (2005). Always having to say youre sorry: An ethical response to making

    mistakes in professional practice.Nursing Ethics, 11(6), 568-576.

    Quotations Page, Eleanor Roosevelt quotes. Retrieved May 11, 2008, from

    http://www.quotationspage.com/quotes/Eleanor_Roosevelt

    Fein, S.P, Hilborne, L.H, Spirtus, E.M., Seymann, G.B., Keenan, C.R., & Shojania, K.G.

    et al. (2007). The many faces of error disclosure: A common set of elements and a

    definition.Journal of General Internal Medicine, 22(6), 755-761.

    Healey, M.A., Shackford, S.R., Osler, T.M., Rogers, F.B. & Burns, E. (2002).

    Complications in surgical patients.Archives of Surgery, 137(5), 611-618.

    The Institute for Safe Medication Practice (ISMP). (2004). Intimidation: Practitioners

    speak up about this unresolved problem (part I). Retrieved May 15, 2008, from

    http://www.ismp.org/Newsletters/acutecare/articles/20040311_2.asp

    The Institute for Safe Medication Practice (ISMP). (2005a). High-reliability

    organizations (HROs): What they know that we dont (Part I) July 14. Retrieved May 4,

    2008, from http:www.ismp.org/newsletters/acutecare/articles/20050714.asp

    15

    http://www.quotationspage.com/quotes/Eleanor_Roosevelthttp://www.ismp.org/Newsletters/acutecare/articles/20040311_2.asphttp://www.quotationspage.com/quotes/Eleanor_Roosevelthttp://www.ismp.org/Newsletters/acutecare/articles/20040311_2.asp
  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    16/18

    The Institute for Safe Medication Practice (ISMP). (2005b). High-reliability

    organizations (HROs): What they know that we dont (Part II) July 28. Retrieved May 4,

    2008, from http:www.ismp.org/newsletters/acutecare/articles/20050728.asp

    Institute of Medicine (IOM), Kohn, K.T., Corrigan, J.M. & Donaldson, M.S. (1999).

    (Ed.) To err is human: Building a safer health system, Washington, D.C.: National

    Academy Press.

    Joint Accreditation Commission Healthcare Organizations (JCAHO).

    (2001).Comprehensive Accreditation Manual for Hospitals: The Official Handbook.

    Oakbrook Terrace, IL: JCAHO.

    Kant, I. (1996).Practical Philosophy. Gregor, M.J. (Trans., ed) Cambridge, NY:

    Cambridge University Press.

    Kelley, G.A. (2005). Living at the sharp end: Moral obligations of nurses in reporting and

    disclosing errors in health care. Critical Care Nursing Clinics of North America, 14(4),

    401-405.

    Kessler, R.C., Berglund, P., Demler, O., Jin, R., Merikangas, K.R., & Walters, E.E.

    (2005). Lifetime prevalence and age-of-onset distributions of DSM-IV disorders in the

    National Comorbidity Survey Replication.Archives of General Psychiatry, 62(6):593-

    602.

    Kidder, R.M. (2005). Moral courage. New York: HarperCollins Publishers.

    Lachman, V. (2007) Moral courage: A virtue in need of development? MEDSURG

    Nursing, 16(2), 131-133.

    16

  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    17/18

    Leape, L.L. (2005). Ethical issues in patient safety. Thoracic Surgery Clinics, 15(4), 493-

    502.

    Leape, L.L. (2006). Full disclosure and apology-An idea whose time has come. The

    Physician Executive, 2, 16-18.

    Mavroudis, C., Mavoudis, C.D., Naunheim, K.S. & Sade, R.M. (2005). Should surgical

    errors always be disclosed to the patient?Annuals of Thoracic Surgery, 80(2), 399-408.

    National Quality Forum. (2003). Safe practices for better health care: A consensus report.

    Report No. NQFCR-05-03. Washington, DC: National Quality Forum.

    Reason, J. (1990). Human error. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Senge, P.M., Kleiner, A., Roberts, C., Roth, G., Ross, R. & Smith, B. (1999). The dance

    of change. New York: Doubleday Business.

    Safer Healthcare. SBAR - A Communication technique for today's healthcare

    professional. Retrieved May 11, 2008, fromhttp://www.saferhealthcare.com/index.php?

    option=com_content&task=view&id=33&Itemid=84

    Sharpe, V.A. (2003). Promoting patient safety: An ethical basis for policy deliberation.

    Hastings Center Report, 33(5), S3-18.

    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (2007). Plato's Ethics: An Overview. Retrieved

    May 15, 2008, from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics/

    Starfield, B. (2000). Is US health really the best in the world?JAMA, 284, 483-4855.

    17

    http://www.saferhealthcare.com/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=33&Itemid=84http://www.saferhealthcare.com/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=33&Itemid=84http://www.saferhealthcare.com/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=33&Itemid=84http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics/http://www.saferhealthcare.com/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=33&Itemid=84http://www.saferhealthcare.com/index.php?option=com_content&task=view&id=33&Itemid=84http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics/
  • 8/6/2019 28_Lachman

    18/18

    18