[2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

download [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

of 24

Transcript of [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    1/24

    1

    Revisiting Complexification, Technology and Urban Form in Lefebvre

    Stephen Read

    Faculty of Architecture

    Delft University of TechnologyJulianalaan 134

    2628 BL Delft

    The Netherlands

    [email protected] (corresponding author)

    Martine Lukkassen

    Yacht

    Charlotte van Pallandtlaan 12

    2272 TR Voorburg

    The Netherlands

    [email protected]

    Tadas Jonauskis

    Spoorsingel 18

    2613 BE, Delft

    The Netherlands

    [email protected]

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    2/24

    2

    Revisiting Complexification, Technology and Urban Form in Lefebvre

    Abstract

    Henri Lefebvre gave suggestive hints at a theory of urban form that have inspired

    those involved in the design and planning disciplines. His search was for an urbanpraxis that opened potentials for new forms of social relations and to this end he

    proposed a metaphilosophy designed to engage with the open-ended material

    relations of cities and societies. This contradicted however his Marxist commitment

    to a finality of man and society and his association of technology with alienation. We

    try here to rethink technology as intrinsic to human and social life: not as means to

    realise thought in the materialisation of spaces and societies, but as medium and

    source, in processes of historical realisation, of orders that comes before thought in

    human practice. We relate this to worlds of practice which are the technically and

    historically constructed metaphilosophical totalities within which we are enabled

    and act. This pluralises and technologises world, and Lefebvres urban form

    becomes a construction of multiple material-technological worlds, each perceived,

    conceived and lived as wholes. These articulate with one another and evolve

    historically. It is the articulations and interfaces between spaces rather than the

    spaces themselves which locate the places of productivity and vitality in the city. The

    question of an open urban shifts subtly from one of resistance to the abstract

    rationalities of planning or an authoritarian state to one of the maintenance of open

    relations between different spaces each with their necessary technical or abstract

    rationalities.

    Keywords

    Lefebvre; urban form; metaphilosophy; complexity; technology; material

    hermeneutics; technoconstruction.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    3/24

    3

    Introduction

    Henri Lefebvre has inspired urban planners and designers with the vivid sense

    his writing gives of a vital and dynamic city implicated with its historical and social

    dimensions. Urban form, which began for Lefebvre with the marking out of an

    abstractspace, religious and political in character, ... evolved [as] a space whichwas relativised and historical (Lefebvre 1991: 48). These spaces were aligned with

    forms of the social through an idea of spatialised praxis so that, for Lefebvre, the city

    and urban life were formed together in an on-going relation and necessary tension

    between the political and the historical. It was this evolved urban space that was the

    source of the vitality and sociability he invoked.

    He emphasised the political dimensions of this production, setting himself

    against the homogenisation and concentrations of power of new abstract, non-

    relativised spaces that he associated in the mid twentieth century with modern

    planning. For him, abstract space negates all differences, those that come from

    nature and history as well as those that come from the body, ages, sexes, and

    ethnicities (Lefebvre 1979: 289). He outlined a critique of the modern urbanism in

    which such spaces were conceived and implemented, but offered only some rather

    obscure hints at how we could turn this critique into a forward thinking urban

    practice. We can however see quite quickly the broad dimensions of what such a

    practice might entail in some of the methods he used. Such a practice would

    certainly not be about the integration of the categories of city and space ... into an

    overarching social theory (Schmid 2006:165); it would lead us rather away from

    general solutions and towards situated processes in which city and society emerged

    together. His concern was that this should happen in ways that enabled people tocreatively form their own existences.

    It is these processes of the production of simultaneously urban and social life

    and power whose intensities and differences are at the same time obscured by the

    normalising and regularising procedures that are an equal part of urban processes

    that we would like to try to begin here to address. We can, we believe, extract from

    Lefebvres ideas suggestive indications of how we might further his project, and

    move positively beyond what was essentially an adventure of the twentieth century

    (Kipfer et al 2008: 2) guided by some very nineteenth century ideas, into one of the

    twenty-first guided by some ideas of the twentieth, ideas Lefebvre in any case

    would have been well aware of. But Lefebvre was a man of his time as much as he

    was ahead of it. His Marxist habits and commitments meant he could not easily

    abandon his critical orientation to a finality of human and societal completion. This

    orientation was made problematic however by his own attempts to open Marxist

    thinking in what he called a metaphilosophy, which involved a concerted

    engagement with the realities of events and developments in a combination of theory

    and praxis. We will identify parallel commitments to materiality and an openness of

    becoming in a hermeneutical philosophy of science and in a contemporary science

    of complexity and use these to understand the shift implied from a dualist

    metaphysics which started with philosophy or theory and regarded thought asoriginary, to an originary logic of inhabitation involving human technique and world.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    4/24

    4

    Lefebvre struggled in particular with a Marxist vision of an alienating

    technology. We will identify another technology that makes it a foundation of all

    social praxis and enablement. This is an idea that suggests also an essential

    historicity and contingency of real-world implementations of technologies.

    Technology here would be neither category nor form in its own right, rathertechnologies would be contingently and strategically enrolled in forms of human and

    social praxis, even while the praxes themselves would be inconceivable without the

    technologies. The concepts we use to represent these forms are those of

    differential and world. We aim to demonstrate how these adjustments to Lefebvres

    thinking may lead relatively seamlessly into, and support his theory of urban form.

    Such a theory will see the urban as a construction of multiple spaces produced in

    different historical moments, formed as differentials of objects, subjects and

    practices, and creating, in their articulations with each other, the characteristic and

    vital places of cities.

    Beyond philosophy

    Lefebvre never intended his writing as a guide for urban planners and

    designers. His was a critical writing, carried out in an open version of Marxism

    (Charnock 2010). There was at the same time however a strong creative or

    constructive theme running through it tied to his conception of space and its

    production. His view of the city was founded around a conception of urban society

    and spatial developments he called mondialisation. He saw changes occurring in

    the conditions of our inhabitation of our planet and saw these developments as tied

    to changes in social and urban relations. He tried to think these issues beyondphilosophy and its speculative abstractions and in relation to an urban society

    embodied in its own material relations (Lefebvre 2003: 64). Urban reality was for him

    something more than a social or political-economic product, it was a productive force

    in its own right, producing social relations as well as expressing them (Lefebvre

    2003: 15).

    Lefebvre criticised structuralist Marxism for its determinism and denial of the

    openings of history and becoming (Elden 2004: 24). He well understood the

    problems of escaping closure and achieving an open praxis in existing models:

    philosophy would, according to Lefebvre, always aim for totality and synthesis,

    attempting to detach its concepts from the contexts and philosophical architectures

    in which they arose (Lefebvre 2003: 63-64). His metaphilosophy on the other hand

    refused a disembodied synthesis and sought to enter into a relationship with the real.

    His method was to get back from the object (product or work) to the activity that

    produced and/or created it. It is the only way ... to illuminate the objects nature, or, if

    you will the objects relationship to nature, and reconstitute the process of its genesis

    and the development of its meaning. All other ways of proceeding can succeed only

    in constructing an abstract objecta model (Lefebvre 1991: 113). His aim was to

    undermine dualisms of structure and agency, theory and practice, and go beyond

    them. Philosophy was no help here. It had, according to Lefebvre, not resolved thecontradictions around the gap between the conceived and the lived.[1] In place of

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    5/24

    5

    the analytical procedures of geography, demography, history, psychology and

    sociology, he proposed we consider the city as a differential, or complex of real

    relations. The differential space Lefebvre proposed was pure form: a place of

    encounter, assembly, simultaneity. This form has no specific content, but is a centre

    of attraction and life. It is an abstraction, but unlike a metaphysical entity, the urbanis a concrete abstraction, associated with practice (Lefebvre 2003: 118-119). This

    form absorbs ... contents ... combines them actively in a totality or virtual synthesis,

    which does not need philosophy for its fulfilment but can simply be recognised as a

    channel (strategy) for action (Lefebvre 2003: 122).

    For Lefebvre any closure of the social portended a marginalisation of civil

    society and its domination by what he called absolute politics, where powerwas

    drained out of everyday sociality and its situations and surrendered to an

    increasingly abstract and authoritarian state and its knowledge institutions. Lefebvre

    refused this imposition of a universal rationality over life, recognising instead the

    autonomy of the practical and material constellations that constituted life. He aimed

    to go also beyond urbanism, which was forhim an ideology that failed to grasp the

    urban because it understood it as a closed system of coded oppositions like public

    and private or work and residence that denied historical becoming and its promise

    of an open sociality. He was concerned with the complexification (Lefebvre 2003:

    45) of an urban social order by which he meant something other than the simple

    complication of things already defined. Rather his concern was the reintegration of

    the perceptual, conceptual and practical dimensions of social life and space.

    Lefebvres call for a right to the city was not just about a right to housing and

    sustenance but the right to the open city and its streets with their spontaneity,sociability and extended networks as means to the open possibilities of life (Lefebvre

    1996). The task of metaphilosophy was to find the instruments to make the urban ...

    more or less the oeuvreof its citizens instead of imposing itself upon them as a

    system, as an already closed book (Lefebvre 1996: 117).

    The totality of his other order was different to the synthesis of theory; it was

    characterised by virtuality, or the way it incorporated the potential of the as yet

    unmade. It was radically open to diverse outcomes constrained only by its material

    and spatiotemporal conditions. With this open-endedness he attempted to break with

    the Marxist-Hegelian progress to societal completion, but also with any social

    construction of reality that makes the social a category already defined. It was the

    social itself, its forms and content, that was the open and uncertain outcome of this

    progress in a spatiotemporal process of urbanisation. However, it was in the

    orientation of his critical thinking to a necessary telos that Lefebvre could not avoid

    closure. He was a political thinker before anything else and his politics was driven by

    the finality of the total or dealienated man (Jay 1984: 295-298), as the end of

    social theory. In fact, in order to open up a view on the productivity of the urban and

    the life of the city, this orientation to a political end the assumption in fact of any

    social or political good before the fact must be necessarily subsumed to this other

    concern of the open urban. There is no open city which guarantees the rights andwell-being of its citizens. Openness and this open right is also openness to failure,

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    6/24

    6

    and to unexpected mishap or disaster. But it is this open productivity that is also

    capable of opening up multifarious types of sociability and action while resisting

    domination. It is with this productivitythat we are concerned. But here, distinctions

    between the lived and the thought, the abstract and the concrete are erased. Spaces

    are not just perceived, they are perceived as moments of practical sense; they arenot just conceived, they are conceived in practice and experience. Osborne and

    Rose are correct to say spaces and the entities they incorporate are experienced as

    much as conceptualised, lived as much as represented. These spaces have a

    materiality which is not merely imagined but is realised (Osborne and Rose 2004:

    212).

    An urban biology

    Lefebvre saw everyday life as the connective tissue that [gave] the totality its

    structure and coherence (Gardiner 2000: 70). This seems from the above to be

    intended to be more than idle metaphor and hints at a discourse around the complex

    sciences of life, of which Lefebvre would have been well aware.[2] Perhaps the

    closest Lefebvre came to a readily recognisable complexity view of the city was in

    his and Rguliers ideas of the polyrhythmy of the city (Lefebvre 2004). Nevertheless

    a sense of an order intrinsic to the materiality and dynamism of the urban world

    pervades his writings and there could be some mileage in looking at him as some

    sort of urban biologist.

    It is, we argue, his concern with a practical engagement with the limits of

    philosophy that Lefebvre shares with a science of complexity, and where we may

    find a convergence with some contemporary biological thinking in which issues ofopenness, construction and technique come to the fore. What the scientist in biology

    deals with are not sciences authoritarian doctrines (Elden 2004: 23) but cases on

    the dissecting table or in the field in an integral and practical process of enquiry that

    involves at once perceiving, conceiving and doing. He or she actively seeks out and

    constructs descriptions of the aspect of reality under investigation. Scientists no

    longer address a system as explained by what they know about it, even if they know

    it perfectly well ... Their questions imply an open situation: what will it be able to

    produce? What kind of behaviour will emerge? And the question must be asked

    each time, with each new situation (Stengers 2004: 96). The scientist finds him or

    herself having to be attentive, tracking, manipulating and describing detailed and

    material processes. He or she is in a situation where models are descriptive and

    provisional, where they change with changing determinations of significance and

    purpose, and where they produce rather than deduce results.

    This sort of biological science recognises both history and the relational nature

    of reality.[3] Isabelle Stengers argues that complexity science is characterised not by

    new theory, but simply by a commitment to asking the questions a reductive science

    cannot answer. These involve the investigator no longer as a detached observer of

    events subject to universal theory, but in involved and open-ended explorations of

    the event spaces of phenomena. This, according to Stengers, implies a newunderstanding of what theory itself means: instead of a theory that limits and defines

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    7/24

    7

    the shape and scope of the problem, and commands it from above or outside the

    action, what is implied here is theory capable of taking on the singular particularities

    of things, and of answering specific questions complex realities impose on us.

    The biological scientist is working with and observing things that already work

    on their own terms. The material under study is already organised and functional at avisceral level and the scientist stands in an interpretive relationship with it. A different

    science recognises complex working arrangements not as representatives of genera

    or abstractions, and their behaviours do not depend at least in the first instance

    on the values human scientists confer upon them. It is the arrangements themselves

    to which our definitions need to be fitted. This is often quite literally a matter of life

    and death as the objects of the science may not be indifferent to their own functions

    and structures. Science is thus a confrontation between human language, which is

    also to say human devices, and non-human creation ... and it is a speculative

    confrontation because it is not life, it is our human languages and devices which are

    put to the test (Stengers 2000: 93-94).

    While in classical science, theory establishes the frame within which effects

    and predictable results are produced, this other science is one where what will

    happen is by its nature uncertain detail matters, and may induce critical variation

    and in general the expectation of the scientist is that events will set the terms of their

    own outcomes in the conditions under which they are investigated.[4] Complexity

    science is, according to Stengers, characterised by interventions and negotiations: it

    is a science of a practical staying in touch with reality through our situated

    constructions and manipulations of it. Reality here is not a product of our categories

    but of a negotiation with our categories and language, which is to say with ourtechniques. Science must, according to Stengers, side with creation (Stengers

    2000: 96); what complexity scientists do is create effects through technique rather

    than affirm invariable laws of nature; this involves them as constructorsrather than

    receivers of nature.

    This involves also a different kind of subject-object relationship: instead of the

    disembodied Cartesian subject, standing apart from an object framed in universal

    laws and an absolute space and time, we have living subjects embedded in

    situations with the objects they are involved with in relations of interpretation. It is the

    embodied formof this enquiry the relation of the scientist with the reality of the

    situation under investigation that Stengers holds up as the frame: the totality of

    perceiving, conceiving and doing that involves subject, object and equipment

    (Stengers 2004: 97). Procedures, models and equipment are means of embodying

    enquiry and realising it and modifying at the same time both subject and object.

    What made this realignment of science around its practice possible what in

    effect allowed us to escape the dualist metaphysics embedded in classical science

    was firstly the realisation that there was no direct or unmediated observation.[5] In a

    hermeneutical philosophy of science, Patrick Heelan collapsed perception and

    conception and proposed there was no substantive distinction between observational

    and theoretical entities (Heelan 1977: 29-30). He proposed further that it is thetechnics (the languages and devices), which define what the scientist sees. The

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    8/24

    8

    observer is in an intentional orientation to highly synthetic local conditions. He or she

    manipulates those conditions, shifting the subject or intention side of the subject-

    object divide into the technical and material conditions in which scientific results

    including practical understanding and observed objects are produced. The scientist

    performs a hermeneutical shift (Heelan 1977: 11) of subjective intention intoobjective equipment so that equipment embodies the intentionality of the

    observational act, and observables are produced.

    Material here does not stand against thought but rather participates practically

    in, and even enables, it. Heelan calls this material structured to intentionality non-

    objective. Model, system and structure are quite different here to the abstractions

    Lefebvre warns against: models do not substitute for reality; rather reality is

    understood through the appropriate use of models (Heelan 1977: 37). We will take

    this material non-objective structuring to be equivalent to space, and note it is a

    product of a metaphilosophy similar to that of Lefebvre.

    Non-objective worlds

    There is a practical holism here of whole situations of technically constructed

    and manipulated material relations creating the conditions for knowledge. One way

    of linking this practical condition of totality back to Lefebvre is through Lefebvres

    notion of world. Lefebvre was not primarily interested in the question of the world as

    a scale of global geopolitics, he was interested in the process of comprehending the

    world as a totality in thought and practice (Elden 2008: 80). A source of this

    emphasis is Marxs concern with realisation but it originates also in Heideggers idea

    that the world ... worlds (Heidegger 1998: 126). This is the world in which thehuman and the world are not related as two separate things, but are both enclosed

    and disclosed together (Fink 1960: 47; 210-211; 232-233; quoted in Elden

    2008a: 51; 53). Elden proposes that globalisation comes after and is made possible

    by this more primitive disclosure of the world, which, following Lefebvre, he calls

    mondialisation. He quotes Kostas Axelos: Globalisation names a process which

    universalises technology, economy, politics, and even civilisation and culture. But it

    remains somewhat empty. The world, as an opening is missing. The world is not the

    physical and historical totality, it is not the more or less empirical ensemble of

    theoretical and practical ensembles. It deploys itself. The thing that is called

    globalisation is a kind of mondialisationwithout the world. (Axelos 2005:27)

    Lefebvres view on technology depends on Marx but it depends also on the

    critique of the alienating power of technology of Axelos (Axelos 1976). In Marx

    technology is a mode of human labour which develops in the context of our

    interactions with nature. Technology is the factor we use to meet our needs and

    further our projects, transforming both nature and ourselves in the process. Our

    increasing knowledge and skills are embedded in tools and machinery which we

    then use to further change and control nature and shape human culture and

    understanding. Man externalises nature in this ongoing development of technique

    and the direction of technical civilization is an accelerating rationalisation andinstrumentalisation with ever more of human society in the service of this production.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    9/24

    9

    Axelos, in a reflection of Heideggers latertechnological thinking, argues that this

    technologically driven history implies the eventual complete technification of nature

    and makes Marxist history the history of the development of technique (Axelos

    2005: 27). The world becomes what technology (as a category, in the singular and

    embodying a technological, calculative rationality) presents and produces. ForAxelos it is technique itself that is alienating and the history of technology is coeval

    with the history of alienation.

    At the same time production in thought in Marx is more primitive than the

    material output that proceeds from thought. This is the significance of Marxs well-

    known axiom about architects and bees in which the architect does what the bee

    cannot: constructs edifices in thought before they are constructed in material. For

    Axelos and Lefebvre, the world is an object of thought in its own terms (Elden

    2008: 83). But the idealised thought implied here is at odds with the materiality of

    situated knowing implied by Stengers and Heelan. In their thinking, what is brought

    to or disclosed in thought will emerge in activity in the material-technical conditions

    which pertain. A practical knowing involves equipment and a questioning of how

    exactly and under what material conditions something is known. It is here our

    metaphysics shifts decisively as technology returns in a different, less categorical

    and more contingent guise. The non-objective structures in which we know and do

    things are brought to existence locally and maintained through technique: these

    structures are technoconstructions(Ihde 1997): totalities constructed and embodied

    in equipment (while being modified and adjusted in time), and never simply thought

    (or theory) embodied or disembodied. This radically pluralises world because the

    world disclosed, in which we are disclosed-enclosed, depends on the particularequipment and technique practically absorbed in particular actions. Here we see

    worlds worlding(becoming world)through technique and equipment, as

    perceiving, conceiving and doing are mediated in practical, synthetic situations. We

    introduce in fact a metaphilosophical basis to the thinking of worlds and the things

    they reveal. It is also clear there is no pre-technological mondialisation it would be

    like suggesting Europeans could have known China before ships and camel-trains!

    We can begin to enrich this view of worlds, and their spaces and times, by

    looking at another concept from biology. In a previous paper (Read 2012) one of us

    argued that the view we outlined earlier of the shifting of intentional structures into

    material has an affinity with Stuart Kauffmans idea of biosphere (Kauffman 2000).

    Researchers in biosemiotics freely mix theory of language and the kind of material

    hermeneutics we have been describing to reconnect communication means and

    meaning through a hermeneutics of the living (Marko et al 2009: 8). Biospheres

    are spaces manipulated and adjusted by the actions of involved beings. They are, in

    Heelans terms, non-objective spaces moulded historically by the collective habits,

    actions and interactions of whole groups or populations of living beings to whom life

    and being matters. This commonly shared field allows mutual games of

    understanding, misunderstanding, cheating and imitation at all levels of the

    biosphere (Marko et al2007: 237). And it is only after habits have beennegotiated, rules settled and artefacts produced, that one can point with the index

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    10/24

    10

    finger and distinguish this and that, to recognise rules, habits, or even objects

    (241). The environment becomes a negotiated creationof the beings environed, who

    shift material (and materially shift) into structures meaningful and usually

    advantageous at individual, group and species levels. What is this shifting if not

    technique? What is it if not culture?It is this pathway of exploration of the adjacent possible (Kauffman 2000) in

    whole worlds that is the key to understanding living beings as participants as well as

    factors in an historical process of constructive inhabitation, and even as the driving

    force of habitat development. Biospheres become totalities integrated across

    different levels of organisation, and the oeuvresof their inhabitants. They are

    worlds of inhabitation, not as reflections of preconceived social or subjective form,

    but as non-objective structures that support internally practices of perceiving,

    conceiving and doing. They are also differentials:pure form ... centre[s] of

    attraction and life (Lefebvre 2003: 118-119). We see also how these spaces are at

    the same time complete and multiple. Each species, each population, each culture,

    each practice, develops its own internal world of inhabitation, which will have

    relations externally with other worlds. We share with other creatures the character

    of living in non-objective worlds of communication and significance and acting and

    reacting within them, choosing for the most part life over death, wellbeing over

    degeneration, and configuring and reconfiguring worlds in the process.

    What does this mean for the body and its relation to worlds? Maurice Merleau-

    Ponty used the examples of the blind mans cane and that of the feather in the ladys

    hat to demonstrate how we engage the world through everyday objects which

    become part of our body-awareness (Merleau-Ponty 1962). We notice these objectsonly when we engage them directly as objects, the rest of the time they are just part

    of us. Is the blind man and his cane a unit as Merleau-Ponty suggests? When the

    blind man and his cane get on the tram are these a unit? If we say yes to both

    these questions the consequence would be again to problematise a mind-centred

    (and spaced see Lefebvre 1991: 172-174) notion of subjectivity and displace action

    and intelligence from the mind to the body and thence to body-technology and body-

    world conjunctions. This seems also to be not foreign to Lefebvre who located the

    spiders intelligence in its unity with its web. This already begins to clarify what a

    metaphilosophical production of space might entail; in particular it suggests the roles

    of technologies and worlds need more detailed, careful and even case by case

    appraisal. Technology is generalised and reduced to a singular rationality in Lefebvre

    in his dependence for these concepts on Marx and Axelos. The different take we

    propose particularisestechnologies and places them at a more strategic and

    contingent level in enabling us as actors and producers of worlds integrated in

    common languages and techniques.

    We could then start to tackle these multiple worlds and the languages and

    techniques internal to them through the semiotics of Greimas. In fact both Lefebvre

    and the biosemioticians Anton Marko and his colleagues do just this. Differential

    spaces produce particularised differences through the indexing of individuals inrelation to each other and to whole communities of individuals. Lefebvre used the

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    11/24

    11

    term isotopy to describe the internal relations affecting mutually indexed individuals.

    Isotopy refers to the fact that elements and their differences are mutually

    contextualised as part of the establishment of a rationale of sense or coherence in

    the whole: it refers ... to constancy in going in a direction that a text exhibits when

    submitted to rules of interpretive coherence (Eco 1986: 201). The classic example isthe words in a sentence which are all different, all contextualised by each other, and

    all contribute through their internal relations to the sense of the individual words and

    of the sentence as a whole.

    Urban form as non-objective worlds

    The urban form Lefebvre somewhat tentatively sets out can be understood

    quite straightforwardly from this point. He speculates on the original city, built as a

    political and dominated space. Political spaces were purposefully constructed and

    abstract, a founding violence (Lefebvre 1991: 280), a positive imposition of order

    against a disordered world. The political city instituted and enforced social order

    (Lefebvre 1991: 285-287). It achieved and sustained a particular view on the world,

    administered, protected and exploited a territory, organised drainage, irrigation and

    the clearing of land for agriculture. It was a place of writing: documents, laws,

    inventories, tax collection but also of procurement and work to support the activities

    of political power (Lefebvre 2003: 8). It constructed spaces that internalised and

    made routine particular practices, languages and techniques and embedded and

    embodied power through these enablements. But dominated spaces were only

    homogeneous and devoid of differences in the first instance (Lefebvre 1991: 240;

    285). They were spaces without life, vulnerable to their own need to be sustained bywhat they excluded and what they dominated. Something irregular always escaped

    domination: against the isotopy of the city was the heterotopy of the border. Space

    ... then ... reintroduces itself subversively through the effects of peripheries, the

    margins, the regions (Lefebvre 1976-78 vol 4: 164-165; quoted in Brenner & Elden

    2009: 360).

    Exchange and trade were initially irregular activities, carried out by itinerants,

    suspicious individuals, ... strangers who acted outside political space. The

    eventual renewal of the city as something more differentiated and complex was

    facilitated and eventually made inevitable by the increasing power of the other

    spaces of the traders and travellers (Lefebvre 2003: 9). These other spaces

    themselves became regularised and affirmed as spaces: the overland, river and sea

    routes of the strangers and itinerants became political spaces on their own account

    by early modern times in Europe, organising, protecting and furthering their own

    activities and interests. The power of the itinerants was transformed as they

    distributed and organised their activities across networks of cities. Cities related

    strategically with one another in an increasingly regularised fashion as new levels of

    political order emerged, each with their own isotopies of related languages,

    techniques and practices, and each with their heterotopies of objects and practices

    standing outside that order, belonging to other spaces. The points of articulation of

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    12/24

    12

    different spaces became heterotopic: in the best cases, places of negotiation and

    exchange between different spaces.

    Political spaces were clearly not constrained by any universalrationality: they

    emerged in different times, and were constructed to specific internalaims, orders

    and rationalities. Political spaces then overlapped and articulated with one anotherand relations between them came to reflect not so much a conflict between the

    regular and the irregular as a negotiation or struggle between different internalised

    orders. This negotiation between levels and spaces of political power resulted in the

    rise of merchant cities in Italy and in Western Europe and the Baltic in early modern

    Europe. It marked, in Lefebvres analysis, a shift in powerfrom the city to the larger

    intercity network as merchants and their spaces of regularised and regulated trade

    moved from the marginal spaces and gateways of cities to take over their most

    central spaces as well (Lefebvre 2003: 10). The trader and his network became

    essential to the growing complexification and productivity of the city. The city leagues

    established networks of trade but also of economic, educational, cultural and other

    practices, including banking systems with credit and exchange norms, exchanges of

    artistic, technological and production practices, and divisions of labour and

    interdependencies across networks of cities. This heralded the emergence of an

    abstract space of capitalist accumulation (Lefebvre 1991: 277-278).

    There are some important spatial mechanisms implied here which make

    problematic our tendency to see space as flat and cartographic. Elements exist in

    relations of isotopy with other elements within a field while they exist in relations of

    heterotopy with elements outside of that field. Sets of elements in isotopic relations

    with one another form fields that are bounded only in the sense that their relationsare internal. There is no necessary literal boundary. An element that was part of a

    trading network in the early modern city was heterotopic with respect to the

    municipal relations of the city, even though that part of the trading network may have

    been geographically inside the city. In this sense heterotopic elements may be both

    inside and outside a city at the same time. This is less strange than it sounds if we

    remember that what defines an element is its relations rather than its position on a

    map. At the same time however cartographic position matters profoundly because

    these places of articulation between spaces are characterised by exchange and

    negotiation and tend to be the most visible and vital parts of cities. An element in a

    city (a harbour for example) may be in isotopic relations with other elements

    (harbours) in other cities and be heterotopic with respect to strictly municipal

    elements and interests in that city. The municipality will exact taxes and levies, and

    will otherwise benefit through the services it provides to ships and sailors. The

    municipality will also host other networks, like that of banking for example. Cities

    become differentiated into layers of practices and politics without being segmented,

    and it is the crossingsof different languages, techniques and practices which define

    places of heterotopic productivity.

    Abstract spaces reduce all intensities to internally calculable quantities, which

    is why from within them the task of understanding the creative and living qualities ofspace becomes difficult or impossible. In fact, isotopy demands that particular

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    13/24

    13

    abstract spaces consistently embed particular rationales. These rationales are not

    universal however; their limits are also the limits of the spaces themselves. Places of

    productive conflict and exchange exist at the interfaces between spaces. It is in

    these heterotopies that we maintain the openness of action and evade the closure of

    rationalities that make claims for universality within their own spaces. The exchangebetween different spaces also establishes however the vivid and identifiable places

    that political power then co-opts to its own interests. It is this organisation and

    articulation of spaces with their creative heterotopies of vivid places that defines

    cities and their forms.

    Insert Figure 1 about here.

    Isotopy and heterotopy in the industrial city

    The construction of isotopic, internally ordered political spaces and their

    consequent heterotopic relations with one another has been the basis of the

    relativised and historical urban form Lefebvre cites (Lefebvre 1991: 48). In more

    recent times the imposition of another political space, produced under the conditions

    of a modern alliance of capitalist industrialisation and social democracy, produced

    the extensions of European cities of the 19th and early 20th centuries. A new space

    was built out from the centres of European centres founded on new normative

    models of social neighbourhood and modern commercial city (van der Woud, 2001:

    194). The city was the site of industrialisation and a growing consumerism which

    introduced different forms of urban life and produced new spaces (Harvey 2006).The new internal rationale of the city facilitated industrial production and

    consumerism. New telephone, electrical, water and sewage systems were

    introduced, and technical systems like public transportation were used to integrate

    city space and organise relations between city and neighbourhood spaces. The

    neighbourhood meanwhile was integrated around grids of public facilities and

    neighbourhood streets while it internalised a new rationale of social community and

    ideals of social welfare and public health. It was in the meeting of spaces of

    industrial-consumerist city and social neighbourhood that new heterotopic centralities

    emerged in linear patterns of shopping streets simultaneously connecting and

    centring neighbourhoods.

    These streets of communal life were the spaces of passing strangers as well as

    the central places of neighbourhoods, of catching the tram and of everyday shopping

    and conviviality. Though the specific contents of neighbourhood and city have

    changed in the hundred or so years since their building, the characteristic pattern is

    still readily recognisable today in Rotterdam, in the bustling streets that trace paths

    through these areas. These still provide a focus for everyday life and display a

    characteristic urban sociability.

    Insert Figure 2 about here.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    14/24

    14

    The imposition of new spaces over existing ones has been the way cities have

    changed and grown in Europe since early modernity. The rapid urbanisation which

    marked industrialisation saw also the arrival of the railway and steam shipping. New

    technical infrastructures connected cities to organise the inter-city logistics of

    industrialisation, while they organised at the same time the locations of industrialsites in or on the edges of cities. This was also a time of nation-building and a first

    globalisation and the new infrastructures saw the consolidation of urban centres as

    national and global places. More recent post-industrial and post-socialist

    developments have been characterised by the rise of private transportation

    supported by new regional (publically-funded) infrastructures. The city has been

    reconfigured into a metropolitan pattern of residential suburbs and commercial,

    business, industrial and recreational centres organised around new motorway

    networks (Bruyns and Read 2008). At each stage of this process new urban objects

    have been enrolled into new political spaces along with new practices and

    technologies. The new spaces themselves defined normativities like modern city,

    social neighbourhood, metropolitan region that represented massive, and mostly

    public, investment in infrastructures and buildings, and were celebrated as planning

    achievements in their own times. Each opened new conditions and opportunities for

    the definition or redefinition of social life and the expansion of capitalism (Harvey

    2001).

    One of the most basic organisational logics of these new normative worlds is

    revealed in the way they presented places to us abstracted and systematised as

    stops in tram, metro or rail systems, airline destinations, turn-offs on motorways, etc.

    These new normative worlds have been integrated in and with transportationsystems so that our relationships with places and with the social and cultural lives

    they embed are mediated through transportation technologies. The European

    historical centre, a place lived in for hundreds of years, has become abstracted to a

    destination in municipal tram, regional bus and national rail systems. It has become

    abstracted as a business and tourist destination in continental and global airline

    systems with shuttle trains and busses completing the link between centre and

    airport. Places are presented to us in place-disclosing equipment and it is through

    this equipment we perceivethe places we act in and towards and even conceive

    what it is they are. The equipment abstracts and acts as model, revealing objects

    and places to us and explicating their logics.

    But there is also nothing particularly new about this: the historical centre in the

    sixteenth century was lived in in much the sense a neighbourhood is lived in today,

    and for anything beyond that this abstraction was a necessary part of the way

    perception, conception and action towards distant places was enabled. Place

    abstraction was a character of the destinations in early modern trading networks,

    and abstraction into particular and regularised times (that of the church bell for

    example, or the train schedule) is a feature of all urban spaces. It is through the way

    perception and conception is mediated as a technologically supported abstraction

    that these worlds present us not only with the means to get from place to place butalso with the practical knowledge that these places exist and they are available to us.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    15/24

    15

    These abstractions are very concrete achievements; reality here is not a concrete

    reflection of an abstract network (Lefebvre 1991: 266), it is the network itself,

    technologically achieved. And at each stage of the development of these concrete

    abstractions new opportunities for heterotopic crossings of spaces occur which have

    precipitated serial changes of use and fortune for centres and other significantplaces in cities over time.

    Insert Figure 3 about here.

    Contemporary isotopy and heterotopy

    Not all these abstract-technological worlds are based around such readily

    recognisable forms. New global information systems are designed to a logic which

    seems at first quite foreign to urban space. The Technical Analysis financial trading

    style for example quite literally collapses space and time into one simultaneous

    global place in order to present the objects of the global financial market real-time to

    traders wherever they are (and have access to a terminal) (Knorr Cetina & Bruegger

    2002: 179-181). In a powerful evocation of Heelans experimental situation, financial

    traders do and see things in a non-objective system acutely tuned to the

    perceptions and conceptions of those accredited to use it. This abstraction is again

    concrete, requiring wires and cables, the appropriate hardware and software, and

    regular updating and maintenance. There is little here that can be glossed or written

    off as an effect of a generalised technology; the space is a specific, highly

    designed, highly secured and technically realised differential. This system and others

    like it also express themselves clearly enough in the heterotopic effects they produce like the clusters of glass-clad towers that soar above their surroundings in the

    downtowns or on the edges of contemporary cities. We see however how the rights

    to the city places produced in these effects are today vigorously and scrupulously

    controlled. The spaces of the electronic networks require highly secured portals and

    interfaces with the spaces of buildings, streets, public transportation systems, hotel,

    entertainment and shopping districts, and so on. Adjoining spaces are carefully

    designed and supervised as issues of security and image and the control of public

    space for dominant interests take precedence over the interests of diversity and

    sociality.

    Conflicts over the right to the city have played themselves out historically at

    strategic locations in the city, and today, as the occupy movement has shown, the

    key places of resistance to the dispossession of this right are global places, right

    there amongst the glass towers. It is difficult to see at this point in time however how

    this knowledge will lead to direct proposals for the permanent reoccupation of the

    city. However, strategic gains will eventually be won through a better understanding

    of the possibilities of technological spaces themselves and strategic modifications of

    their relations. The mechanisms of power and enablement exist at multiple scales

    and in multiple spaces so that there are multiple locations at which rights can be

    fought for and won. In order to achieve this better understanding we need especiallyto question interpretations of contemporary developments that miss both the

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    16/24

    16

    historical depth and the situated and visceral materiality of processes of power,

    enablement and urbanisation. The generalised global space that is a feature of

    much contemporary discussion, is again a product of a generalised technology in

    this case one that is new, high-tech and virtual (Wellman 2001; Castells 1989;

    1996). What we have suggested instead is that technologies have a hand in thedifferential and virtual nature of all spaces and that we are enabled and emplaced,

    through these spaces. Access to spaces of enablement is a vital factor of power

    while opportunities for escaping the closure of these spaces come from the ways

    they articulate with other spaces. We have suggested that we inhabit, and always

    have, a layered construction of technological spacesworlds that articulate with

    each other, and that it is these located articulations and interfaces rather than the

    spaces themselves which underpin the places of open creativity and vitality of the

    city.

    This knowledge also allows us to critique what Don Mitchell calls the

    annihilation of space by law (Mitchell 2002) the managers of the spaces of the new

    economy have turned to in order to make urban centres attractive to footloose

    capital. As Mitchell points out, the ideology of globalisation is a way of masking the

    degree to which capital must be located. It masks, whats more, the dependency of

    any urban function and indeed any human action on spaces inherited from deep in

    human and urban history. The rights to this human patrimony is a matter of simple

    justice; the good sense of maintaining its openness lies in recognising that

    exclusionary and sanitised spaces limit social possibilities and repertoires and

    engender fearful and unimaginative citizens and societies. A clearer understanding

    of the urban form Lefebvres methods suggest, puts us in a position to critique someof these developments and propose alternative urbanisms that promote no particular

    space or rationality but find productive articulations between different spaces and

    rationales, in open engagements with the future.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    17/24

    17

    Notes

    1. In his work these dichotomies were tactical devices, the task of which was to

    demonstrate their limitations and to transcend them (Lefebvre 1991: 405-6).

    2. He would have been familiar for example with the ideas of Edgar Morin.

    3. He would have been familiar for example with the ideas of Edgar Morin.4. This problematises our assumptions about transformation: both Eldredge and

    Gould and Kauffman have argued against gradualism as a mode of biological or

    ecological change, arguing instead for punctuated equilibrium (Eldredge and Gould

    1985) and a holism (Kauffman 1995) in which changes require shifts from one whole

    differential form to another adjacent possible form, the whole forms themselves

    tending towards stability.

    5. Mediation becomes synonymous with knowledge there is no knowledge without

    a mediating world and it is the world (and the subjects intentional stance towards

    it) that mediates. The historical dimension leaves knowledge open through new

    worlds and stances.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    18/24

    18

    References

    Axelos, K. (1976) Alienation and Techne in the Thought of Karl Marx, (Austin:

    University of Texas Press)

    Axelos, K. (2005) Mondialisation without the World: Interviewed by Stuart Elden,

    Radical Philosophy, No 130, 25-28Brenner, N. & S. Elden (2009) Henri Lefebvre on State, Space, Territory,

    International Political Sociology 3, 353-377

    Bruyns, G. & S.A. Read The Form of the Metropolitan Territory: the case of

    Amsterdam and its periphery in: H.C. Bekkering, A. ten Doeschate, D.

    Hauptmann, A.C. den Heijer, U. Knaack & S. van Manen (eds.), The

    Architecture Annual 2006-2007 (Rotterdam: 010 Publishers).

    Castells, M. (1989) The Informational City: Information Technology, Economic

    Restructuring, and the Urban Regional Process (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Castells, M. (1996) The Rise of the Network Society, The Information Age: Economy,

    Society and Culture Vol. I (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Charnock, G (2010) 'Challenging New State Spatialities: The Open Marxism of Henri

    Lefebvre', Antipode, 42, 1279-1303.

    Eco, U. (1986) Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language (Bloomington: Indiana

    University Press)

    Elden, S. (2004) Understanding Henri Lefebvre: Theory and the Possible (London:

    Continuum).

    Elden, S. (2008) Mondialisation before globalization: Lefebvre and Axelos, in, K.

    Goonewardena, S. Kipfer, R. Milgrom, C. Schmid (eds.), Space, difference,

    everyday life : reading Henri Lefebvre (Abingdon: Routledge), 80-93.Elden, S. (2008a) Eugen Fink and the Question of the World, in Parrhesia 5, 48-59.

    Eldredge, N. and S.J. Gould (1985) Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic

    gradualism in, N. Eldredge Time frames (Princeton: Princeton University

    Press) 193-223

    Fink, E. (1960) Spiel als Weltsymbol (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer)

    Gardiner, M. (2000) Critiques of everyday life: An introduction (London: Routledge)

    Harvey, D. (2001) Globalization and the spatial fix Geographische Revue, 2, 23-

    30.

    Harvey, D. (2006) The political economy of public space in: S. Low & N. Smith

    (eds.) The Politics of Public Space (London; Routledge)

    Harvey, D. (2008) The Right to the City New Left Review 53, 23-40

    Heelan P. (1977) Hermeneutics of Experimental Science in the Context of the Life-

    World, in D. Ihde & R.M. Zaner (eds.) Interdisciplinary Phenomenology,

    (Martinus Nijhoff: The Hague), 7-50.

    Heidegger, M. (1998) Pathmarks, ed. W. McNeill (Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press)

    Ihde, D. (1997) Thingly hermeneutics/Technoconstructions, Man and World 30 pp.

    369-381.

    Jay, M. (1984) Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukacs toHabermas (Cambridge: Polity)

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    19/24

    19

    Kauffman, S.A. (1995) At Home in the Universe: The Search for Laws of Self-

    Organization and Complexity (Oxford: Oxford University Press)

    Kauffman, S.A. (2000) Investigations (Oxford: Oxford University Press)

    Kipfer, S., K. Goonewardena, C. Schmid, R. Milgrom (2008) On the production of

    Henri Lefebvre, in: K. Goonewardena, S. Kipfer, R. Milgrom, C. Schmid (eds.),Space, difference, everyday life : reading Henri Lefebvre (Abingdon:

    Routledge) 1-23

    Knorr Cetina, K. and U. Bruegger (2002) Traders Engagement with Markets: A

    Postsocial Relationship, Theory, Culture & Society, 19 (5/6), 161-185.

    Lefebvre, H. (1979) Space: Social Product and Use Value in Critical Sociology:

    European Perspectives, (ed. and trans. J.W. Freiberg) (New York: Irvington

    Publishers).

    Lefebvre, H. (1991) The Production of Space, trans by Donald Nicholson-Smith

    (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Lefebvre, H. (1991b) Critique of Everyday Life: Volume One, trans. J. Moore, (New

    York: Verso).

    Lefebvre, H. (1996) The Right to the City, in Writings on Cities, trans. and ed. by E.

    Kaufman and E. Lebas (Oxford: Blackwell) 61-181

    Lefebvre, H. (2003) The Urban Revolution, trans. R. Bonnano, (Minneapolis:

    University of Minnesota Press)

    Lefebvre, H. (2004) Rhythmanalysis: Space , Time and Everyday Life, trans. S.

    Elden & G. Moore (London: Continuum).

    Marko, A., F. Grygar, K. Kleisner, & Z. Neubauer (2007) Towards a Darwinian

    Biosemiotics. Life as Mutual Understanding, in: M. Barbieri (ed.) Introduction toBiosemiotics: The New Biological Synthesis, (Dordrecht: Springer)

    Marko, A. F. Grygar, L. Hajnal, K. Kleisner, Z. Kratochvl & Z. Neubauer (2009) Life

    as Its Own Designer: Darwins Origin and Western Thought, (Dordrecht

    Springer)

    Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962) Phenomenology of Perception trans. C. Smith (London:

    Routledge)

    Mitchell, D. (2002) The Annihilation of Space by Law: The Roots and Implications of

    Anti-Homeless Laws in the United States, Antipode 29 (3) pp. 303-335

    Osborne, T. and N. Rose (2004) Spatial phenomenotechnics: making space with

    Charles Booth and Patrick Geddes, Environment and Planning D: Society and

    Space, 22, pp. 209-222

    Read, S.A. (2012) Meaning and material: phenomenology, science and adjacent

    possible cities in: J. Portugali et al. (eds.), Complexity Theories of Cities Have

    Come of Age (Berlin: Springer-Verlag) pp. 105-127

    Schmid C. (2006) Networks, Borders, Differences: Towards a Theory of the Urban.

    In: R Diener et al. (eds) Switzerland: An Urban Portrait, (Basle: Birkhauser)

    164173.

    Stengers, I. (2000), Gods Heart and the Stuff of Life Pli 9, 86-118

    Stengers, I. (2004) The challenge of complexity: Unfolding the ethics of science. Inmemoriam Ilya Prigogine E:CO 6(1-2), 92-99

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    20/24

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    21/24

    21

    Figure 1.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    22/24

    22

    Figure 2.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    23/24

    23

    Figure 3.

  • 8/2/2019 [2010] Revisiting Lefebvre final draft

    24/24

    Figure 1. Fragment of: Cornelis Anthonisz. Bird's eye view of Amsterdam. 1544.

    Woodcut. Rijksmuseum Amsterdam. The gate at the centre of the drawing, the

    Nieuwmarkt, was and remains one of the major market places of the city. The

    markets at the city gates in 16th century Amsterdam marked the points of articulation

    of regional networks and internal city space. The harbour marked the point ofcrossing of Baltic and North Sea trading networks and city space. Within a century

    the Nieuwmarkt would be immersed in the fabric of the expanding city while it

    continued orchestrating activity around itself, retaining its market function and a

    vitality and vividness as a place in the city. The harbour area has likewise continued

    to orchestrate relations between the city and the larger networks of which the city is

    a part.

    Figure 2. 3 neighbourhoods in Rotterdam mapped for everyday events (red dots).

    The patterns of the heterotopic main streets, interfacing the spaces of

    neighbourhood and city, are clear to see.

    Figure 3. Kaunas, Lithuania: a. 1915 b. 1990 c. 2010. At each of these dates a

    different technological space was dominant (a neighbourhood scale grid of walking in

    the main; a state-sponsored public transportation network; a regional motorway

    network) and the city was configured around these worlds. No world ever

    completely disappears unless it is literally erased so a. was still operating vestigially

    in b. while a. and b. were operating vestigially in c. But relatively high-tech examples

    replace lower-technologies that allowed us to use and know the city in different

    ways. There is a process of innovation and replacement in the making human of theplanet which sees camels replaced by airlines and railways and the carvel and fluit

    by the container ship. Networks and places already made are taken into new

    dominant spaces while being reconfigured and transformed. At each stage of

    innovation previous heterotopic places (as the most vivid and activity and

    opportunity-rich places will usually be appropriated into the new spaces.