1 Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and...
date post
19-Apr-2018Category
Documents
view
217download
1
Embed Size (px)
Transcript of 1 Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and...
1
Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and Critical Social Theory
John Grant Department of Politics
Queen Mary, University of London [email protected]
Presented at the CPSA Annual Conference May 31-June 3 2005
University of Western Ontario,
*Any use or reproduction of this work requires prior consent of the author*
2 Introduction
This paper interrogates work by Louis Althusser within the larger context of an ongoing
study into the efficacy of a dialectical approach to critical social theory. Althussers work
occupies a productive place in twentieth century thought: it rejects the existential humanism of
Sartre, while upholding the type of determinate political positions sometimes abandoned by
poststructuralists such as Foucault or Derrida. My aim is to read Althusser predominantly
against himself in order to rework and relocate his rendering of the dialectic. Althussers
conception of the Marxist dialectic suffers, as I will show, from a number of conceptual
deficiencies. Not only does it seem to reproduce the same type of economism he wanted to
avoid, it overemphasizes the role of structural determinants. By refusing to employ any concept
of the subject the conditions of dialectical analysis are lost, along with the possibility of
accounting for political questions concerning experience and resistance.
I believe that for social theory the real promise of Althussers thought lies in developing a
more rigorous dialectical approach. The following is one way of envisioning the route this might
take. 1) Refusing, unlike Althusser, to overemphasize the homogeneity of any ideological
conjuncture, so that one can begin to identify the contradictory ways in which we are produced
as subjects; 2) Maintaining the category of the subject over against Althussers strict anti-
humanism, which allows one to recognize the movements and rhythms of a subject-object
dialectic; 3) Althussers posthumously published work identifies what he terms aleatory
materialism. It places significant importance on the encounter as a moment of ontological
becoming that is open and multiple. By emphasizing the singularity of every encounter
3 alongside the insights of (1) and (2), a dialectical approach is produced that allows the subject to
identify the contradictory elements of its own, always incomplete, production. Finally, and most
significantly, these elements can then be recast as points of resistance within a larger critical
social theory.
I - Althussers Marxist Dialectic
Althussers project of constructing a so-called scientific Marxism relies on using the
concepts, according to him, that Marx developed as a way of understanding the historical
development of social formations as a process without a subject. Often Althusser explicates his
version of a Marxist dialectic by counterposing it to Hegels conception of dialectics. For
example, the conception of an overdetermined contradiction is played off against simple one,
which is based on the notion of an original unity that can be restored. Overdetermination implies
that at any given moment society is characterized by multiple contradictions that are themselves
the result of a multitude of different constituent elements (or at least more than two). The
distinguishing feature of this complexity is a structure in dominance that assumes the principal
role in organizing and articulating the specific form of any social whole (Althusser, 1969: 200-
02). Althusser calls the structure in dominance the most profound characteristic of the Marxist
dialectic (1969: 206). This dominance is responsible for the uneven and overdetermined
development of the structures that constitute the social whole, which is what delineates a
specifically Marxist contradiction. In any social formation the economy is the dominant structure,
although, famously, it is only dominant in the last instance (Althusser, 1969: 217). This feature
of the dialectic is not only a reality for Althusser, but is required in order to . . . escape the
4
arbitrary relativism of observable displacements by giving these displacements the necessity of a
function (Althusser and Balibar, 1970: 99). If the economy is only dominant in the last instance,
this means that it is possible for a different structure to be dominant at any other instance, albeit
for economic reasons. Indeed, Althusser goes so far as to claim that, From the first moment to
the last, the lonely hour of the last instance never comes (1969: 113). This is what invests
overdetermination with such theoretical importance. At any given moment the structures that
make up the social whole constitute a complex unity, which is governed by a specific structure in
dominance. The productivity of overdetermination rests in the notion that the specific shape of a
social formation is constantly developing (in response to the dominant structure), which requires
an infinite return to the specific moment of conjuncture in order to articulate its form.
The apparent tension in Althusser, between an emphasis on rather rigid structures and
each singular social formation that they compose, is not necessarily as great as it might seem.
There is a certain implicit, continual movement, from one position to the other, even if for now
the concern with structures seems to take priority. The explanatory priority of structures cannot
be understood apart from Althussers rejection of humanism and the category of the subject,
which he identifies as a major difference between the Hegelian and Marxist dialectics. Althusser
invested great energy in his opposition to Hegelian and existentialist Marxists like Herbert
Marcuse and Jean-Paul Sartre, whom he saw as humanists trapped in a philosophy of the subject
and consciousness (see Althusser, 1976: 99, 188). The following quotation introduces Althussers
notion of ideology, and helps to explain why humanism is an ideological concept.
In ideology men do indeed express, not the relation between them and their conditions of existence, but the way they live the relation between them and their conditions of existence: this presupposes both a real and an imaginary, lived relation . . . In ideology
5 the real relation is inevitably invested in the imaginary relation, a relation that expresses a will (conservative, conformist, reformist or revolutionary), a hope or a nostalgia, rather than describing a reality (1969: 233-34).
The humanist idea of the subject contains what Althusser calls the theoretical characters cast in
this ideological scenario, which include the philosophical Subject (the philosophizing
consciousness), the scientific Subject (the knowing consciousness), and the empirical Subject (the
perceiving consciousness) . . . (1970: 54-5). Althusser is rejecting any notion of a constitutive
subject that acts as the source of its own thoughts and actions. The humanist subject is
ideological because it imagines that it controls its surroundings, that its relationship to its
conditions of existence is shaped, first and foremost, by its ability to make unrestricted and
transparent personal choices. Further, humanist notions of the subject necessarily rely on some
idea of human essence, and therefore origin. To wit, humans have an original essence from which
they are currently estranged or alienated; our foremost considerations, then, must be devoted to
reestablishing conditions that allow this essence to become knowable, and flourish. This is the
basis on which Marxs early work is often judged. Althussers well-known claim is that there is
an epistemological break in Marxs work around 1845 (and in The German Ideology specifically)
that signalled the end of his flirtations with the humanist anthropology of Hegel and Feuerbach.1
Quite simply, when it comes to understanding social relations and change, the individual, or the
category of the subject, is an inadequate unit of analysis (indeed an ideological one) compared
with, say, classes, or the mode and relations of production,. Political and historical change, then,
must be thought as a process without a subject.
In typically provocative fashion, Althusser writes that Marxs theoretical anti-humanism
constitutes a philosophical revolution. It is impossible to know anything about men except on
6 the precondition that the philosophical (theoretical) myth of man is reduced to ashes (1969:
229).2 This has direct implications for the dialectic. While Althussers concept of
overdetermination contains a specific understanding of complex contradiction between structural
relations, it can no longer be articulated using the concepts of subject and object. Because he
thinks the socio-political field as a series of objects, any claim to knowledge must be posed . . .
in terms which exclude any recourse to the ideological solution contained in the ideological
characters Subject and Object, or to the mutual mirror-recognition structure, in the closed circle of
which they move (1970: 55). Althusser is hostile to any counter-argument that there is always a
mediating term or element that displaces the simple subject-object dichotomy (subjectivity and
labour are two terms that play