On the Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees of the Computably

Post on 23-Feb-2022

3 views 0 download

Transcript of On the Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees of the Computably

On the Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees of theComputably Enumerable Sets

Klaus Ambos-Spies

University of HeidelbergInstitut fur Informatik

Mal’tsev Meeting 2011Novosibirsk, 11 October 2011

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 1 / 29

Strongly Bounded Turing Reducibilities

Notions of bounded Turing reducibilities have been introduced by imposingbounds b(x) on the admissible sizes of the oracle queries in a Turingreduction A(x) = ΦB(x):

b(x) computable: weak truth-table (wtt) or bounded Turing (bT)

b(x) = id(x) = x : identity bounded Turing (ibT)

b(x) = id(x) + c = x + c : strong weak truth-table (cl) or computableLipschitz (cl)

We refer to ibT and cl as the strongly bounded Turing (sbT) reducibilities.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 2 / 29

Origins and Applications

ibT-Reducibility was introduced by Soare (2004) in the context ofsome applications of computability theory to differential geometry(Nabutovski and Weinberger).

cl-Reducibility was introduced by Downey, Hirschfeldt and LaForte(2001) in the context of computable randomness.

Note that, for a set A which is cl-reducible to a set B, the Kolmogorovcomplexity of A � n is bounded by the Kolmogorov complexity of B � nup to an additive constant.

Moreover, Downey, Hirschfeldt and LaForte have shown that, on the

computably enumerable (c.e.) sets, cl-reducibility coincides with Solovay

reducibility which may be viewed as a relative measure of the speed by

which a real number can be effectively approximated by rational numbers.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 3 / 29

Strongly bounded Turing reductions and c.e. sets

Here we will discuss the strongly bounded Turing reducibilities on thecomputably enumerable (c.e.) sets and the corresponding degreestructures.

For any reducibility r , the r -degree of a set A is defined by

degr (A) = {B : B =r A}

An r -degree is called computably enumerable (c.e.) if it contains ac.e. set.

The partial ordering of the c.e. r -degrees is denoted by (Rr ,≤)(where degr (A) ≤ degr (B) if A ≤r B).

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 4 / 29

Examples of ibT-Reductions among c.e. sets

Some typical, frequently used examples of ibT-reductions on the c.e. setsare the following.

Permittingx ∈ Aat s ⇒ ∃ y ≤ x (y ∈ Bat s)

SplittingA = B ∪ C ⇒ B ≤ibT A and C ≤ibT A

In fact, for r = ibT, cl,

degr (A) = degr (B) ∨ degr (C )

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 5 / 29

Relations to the Classical Strong Reducibilities

The strongly bounded Turing reducibilities are incomparable (evenincompatible) with the truth-table type reducibilites.

THEOREM (AS ta). There are noncomputable c.e. sets A and Bsuch that

I for r ∈ {1,m,btt, tt}, A <r BI for r ′ ∈ {ibT, cl}, B <r ′ A

Just as the classical strong reducibilities, the strongly bounded Turingreducibilities are more sensitive to structural properties of c.e. setsthan the weak reducibilities (bT, T). An example:

THEOREM (AS). There is a noncomputable c.e. set which is notcl-equivalent to any simple set (whereas any noncomputable c.e. set isbT-equivalent to a simple set).

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 6 / 29

Strongly Bounded Turing Reducibilites and ComputableInvariance

The strongly bounded Turing reducibilities are not computablyinvariant.

THEOREM (AS). For any noncomputable c.e. set A there are c.e.sets A+ and A− such that the following hold.

I A, A+ and A− are computably isomorphic.

I For r ∈ {ibT, cl}, A− <r A <r A+.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 7 / 29

Separation of ibT, cl and bTTHEOREM (Downey, Hirschfeldt and Laforte 2001, Barmpalias and Lewis2006). Let A be a noncomputable c.e. set.

For A + 1 = {x + 1 : x ∈ A},

A + 1 <ibT A whereas A + 1 =cl A.

For 2A = {2x : x ∈ A},

2A <cl A whereas 2A =bT A.

PROOF.

A ≤ibT A + 1 ⇒ A selfreducible(i.e., A � x computes A(x))

⇒ A computable

(And, similarly, for A ≤cl 2A.)

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 8 / 29

The Partial Orderings of the C.E. ibT- and cl-Degrees((RibT,≤) and (Rcl,≤)) and Their Theories

THEOREM (AS). For r = ibT, cl,

Th(Rr ,≤) is undecidable.

Th(Rr ,≤) realizes infinitely many 1-types (hence is countablycategorical).

So - just as the other degree structures of the c.e. sets, for which thecorresponding results have been previously proven - the partial orderings ofthe c.e. sbT-degrees are rich and complicated structures.

Still the partial orderings of the c.e. ibT/cl-degrees look quite differentthan the partial orderings of the c.e. bT/T-degrees.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 9 / 29

ibT/cl vs. bT/T: First Examples of Similarities andElementary Differences

For r ∈ {ibT, cl,bT,T}, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) possesses a leastelement, namely the degree 0 of the computable sets.

For r ∈ {bT,T}, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) possesses a greatestelement, namely the degree 0′r of the r -complete sets (= the r -degreeof the halting problem).

For r ∈ {ibT, cl}, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) does not possess anymaximal elements (Barmpalias 05 (for cl)).

PROOF for ibT. For noncomputable A, A <ibT A− 1 whereA− 1 = {x − 1 : x ≥ 1 & x ∈ A}.

PROOF for cl (AS, Ding, Fan, Merkle; Belanger). For noncomputablec.e. A, fix an infinite computable subset R of A, let A = A \ R and letA be the compressed version of A obtained by mapping ω \ R onto ω.Then A =ibT A <cl A.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 10 / 29

ibT/cl vs. bT/T: Further Elementary Differences andSimilarities

For r ∈ {bT,T}, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) is an upper semi-lattice:

degr (A) ∨ degr (B) = degr (A⊕ B)

where A⊕ B = {2n : n ∈ A} ∪ {2n + 1 : n ∈ B}.

For r ∈ {ibT, cl}, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) is not a u.s.l.(Barmpalias 05, Fan and Lu 05).

In fact, Barmpalias 05 and Fan and Lu 05 proved that there aremaximal pairs in the partial ordering (Rr ,≤), i.e., c.e. r -degrees a andb such that there is no c.e. r -degree c such that a,b ≤ c.

For r ∈ {ibT, cl,bT,T}, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) is not a lowersemi-lattice (Lachlan, Jockusch, Downey and Hirschfeldt (andothers)).

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 11 / 29

ibT/cl vs. bT/T: Further Elementary Differences andSimilarities

For r ∈ {ibT, cl,bT,T}, every nonzero degree splits, i.e., isjoin-reducible (Sacks’s Splitting Theorem)

For r ∈ {bT, ibT, cl}, every (incomplete) degree is branching, i.e., ismeet-reducible (Ladner and Sasso; AS, Bodewig, Kraling, Yu).

Whereas there are nonbranching c.e. T-degrees (Lachlan).

For r ∈ {bT,T}, (Rr ,≤) is dense (Sacks’s Density Theorem).

Whereas, for r ∈ {ibT, cl}, (Rr ,≤) is not dense (Barmpalias andLewis 10, Day ta).

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 12 / 29

Elementary Differences: Recent Research

The preceding examples show that there are numerous striking differencesbetween the partial orderings of the c.e. ibT- and cl-degrees and thepartial orderings of the c.e. bT- and T-degrees. On the other hand wehaven’t seen any elementary differences between the partial orderings ofthe c.e. ibT-degrees and the c.e. cl-degrees.

In the remainder of my talk I want to present some recent results andopen problems related to the following questions.

On what (logical) complexity level do differences between ibT/cl andbT/T occur?

I Embedding Problem (for finite lattices)

Are the partial orderings (RibT,≤) and (Rcl,≤) elementarilyequivalent?

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 13 / 29

The ∃∗- and ∀∗∃∗-Theories

For r ∈ {ibT, cl,bT,T}, the ∃∗- (or Σ1-) Theories coincide.

This follows from Sacks’s Theorem on independent sequences in thec.e. Turing degrees which implies that all finite partial orderings canbe embedded (as partial orderings) into (Rr ,≤).

This determines ∃∗ − Th(Rr ,≤) and shows that this theory isdecidable.

On the other hand:

For r ∈ {ibT, cl} and r ′ ∈ {bT,T}, the ∀∃-Theories of (Rr ,≤) and(Rr ′ ,≤) differ by the nonexistence/existence of a greatest degree.

The decidability of ∀∗∃∗ − Th(Rr ,≤) seems to be open in all cases.

For a finer analysis we consider existential sentences in richer languagesobtained by adding (relational) symbols for joins and meets (and 0).(NB. The existential theories in these augmented languages are subtheoriesof the forall-exists-theories in the language of partial orderings).Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 14 / 29

The ∃∗-Theories in the languages L(≤,∨,∧) andL(≤,∨,∧, 0)

A decision procedure for ∃∗ − Th(Rr ,≤,∨,∧) and ∃∗ − Th(Rr ,≤,∨,∧, 0)requires an answer to the following

EMBEDDING PROBLEM FOR (Rr ,≤). Which finite lattices can beembedded into (Rr ,≤) as lattices (by a map which preserves the leastelement)?

The Embedding Problem for (RbT,≤) is solved, while the EmbeddingProblem for (RT,≤) is one of the longlasting open problems about thisdegree structure. The Embedding Problem for the strongly boundedTuring reducibilities has been attacked only very recently.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 15 / 29

The Embedding Problem for Distributive Lattices

The Embedding Problem for Distributive Lattices has been completelysolved by Lachlan-Thomason and Lerman by a rather straightforwardvariant of the minimal pair technique.

THEOREM (Lachlan, Thomason, Lerman). The countable atomlessBoolean algebra can be embedded into (RT,≤) (as a lattice) by a mapwhich preserves the least element.

Inspection of the proof (together with some general observations) showsthat the result holds for the other reducibilities (considered here) too.

COROLLARY. For r ∈ {ibT, cl, bT,T}, every countable distributivelattice can be lattice-embedded into (Rr ,≤) by a map which preserves theleast element.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 16 / 29

The Embedding Problem for (RbT,≤)

Since Lachlan has shown that the u.s.l. of the c.e. bT-degrees isdistributive, the universal embedding result for distributive latticescompletely solves the Embedding Problem for (RbT,≤):

THEOREM (Lachlan, Thomason, Lerman). For a finite (or countable)lattice L the following are equivalent.

1 L is distributive.

2 L is embeddable into (RbT,≤).

3 L is embeddable into (RbT,≤) by a map which preserves the leastelement.

In contrast to (RbT,≤), however, the partial orderings (RT,≤), (RibT,≤)and (Rcl,≤) are nondistributive. So there the solution of the EmbeddingProblem requires the by far more sophisticated analysis of thenondistributive lattices.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 17 / 29

Embedding Nondistributive Lattices into (RT,≤)

THEOREM (Lachlan 1972). The nondistributive 5-element lattices M5

(modular) and N5 (nonmodular) are embeddable into (RT,≤) by mapspreserving 0.

• ••

••

66666666666

�����������

�����������

66666666666 66666666666

|||||||||

�����������

BBBBBBBBB

Since any nondistributive lattice contains a copy of the M5 or N5,Lachlan’s result was considered for a while as an indication that all finitelattices can be embedded. But ...

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 18 / 29

A Nonembeddable Lattice for (RT,≤)

THEOREM (Lachlan and Soare 1980). The lattice S8 cannot beembedded into (RT,≤).

•• •

• •

::::::::::

����������

����������

::::::::::

8888888

�������

�������

8888888

(I.e., for any embedding of the M5 into the c.e. Turing degrees, the top isnonbranching.)

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 19 / 29

Current Status of the Embedding Problem for (RT,≤)

AS and Lerman (1986, 1989) have given very general embeddabilityand nonembeddability criteria (EC, NEC).

Lempp and Lerman (1997) give a nonembeddable 20-element latticenot covered by the previous NEC.

Lerman (2006) gives a Π02-characterization of the finite embeddable

lattices without “critical triples”.

Despite these successes, the Embedding Problem for (RT,≤) is stillopen.

All lattices which have been proven to be embeddable are embeddablepreserving the least element. So it has been conjectured thatembeddability and embeddability preserving 0 coincide.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 20 / 29

The Embedding Problem for the C.E. sbT-Degrees: AFirst StepFirst results on the embeddability of nondistributive lattices into thepartial orderings (Rr ,≤) for the strongly bounded Turing reducibilitiesr = ibT, cl have been obtained by AS, Bodewig, Kraling, and Yu:

1 The nondistributive nonmodular lattice N5 is embeddable into(Rr ,≤). (So, in particular, the partial ordering (Rr ,≤) is neitherdistributive nor modular.)

2 Every c.e. r -degrees is the least element of an embedding of the2-atom Boolean Algebra.

3 The finite lattices embeddable into (Rr ,≤) differ from the finitelattices embeddable into (RT,≤). Namely, by the precedingobservation M5 is embeddable into (Rr ,≤) if and only if S8 isembeddable into (Rr ,≤).

4 The nondistributive modular lattice M5 cannot be embedded into(Rr ,≤) by a map which preserves the least element.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 21 / 29

The Embedding Problem for the C.E. sbT-Degrees: MoreRecent Work

AS and Wang (in 2010) have given a (sufficient) criterion for thenonembedabbility by maps preserving 0 (which is based on the dual of“critical triples” which were previously introduced in the context ofNEC).

They also have given an example of a finite (nonmodular) latticewhich can be embedded into (Rr ,≤) (for r = ibT, cl) but whichcannot be embedded by a map preserving 0.

More recently (in 2011), the question of the embeddability of themodular lattice M5 has been resolved:

THEOREM (AS, Bodewig, Kraling, and Wang). M5 is embeddableinto (RibT,≤) and (Rcl,≤).

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 22 / 29

The Embedding Problem for the C.E. sbT-Degrees: OpenProblems

Since we couldn’t find any principal obstacles to embedding latticesinto the partial orderings (RibT,≤) and (Rcl,≤), we conjecture:

CONJECTURE. Any finite lattice can be embedded into (RibT,≤)and (Rcl,≤).

A characterization of the lattices which can be embedded preserving 0seems to be more difficult.

OPEN PROBLEM. What finite lattices can be embedded into(RibT,≤) and (Rcl,≤) by maps preserving 0.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 23 / 29

(RibT,≤) vs. (Rcl,≤): an Elementary Difference

It seems that (RibT,≤) and (Rcl,≤) share the most basic algebraicproperties.

All of the discussed proofs of structural properties of (RibT,≤) could beextended to (Rcl,≤) though the arguments became somewhat (or, in veryfew cases, more than somewhat) more technical and involved.

In fact, in many cases, the proof of the results for (Rcl,≤) could bereduced to the case of (RibT,≤) (e.g. maximal and minimal pairs in bothstructures coincide and (not directly related to the degree structure) a c.e.set is cl-equivalent to a simple set if and only if it is ibT-equivalent to asimple set).

There is a concept, however, which is important for the analysis ofibT-reducibility and which has no direct counterpart in cl-reducibility,namely finite (or bounded) shifts.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 24 / 29

(RibT,≤) vs. (Rcl,≤): Finite Shifts vs. Computable shifts

As we have observed already, for any noncomputable set A,A + 1 <ibT A. By iteration,

· · · <ibT A + 2 <ibT A + 1 <ibT A <ibT A− 1 <ibT A− 2 <ibT . . .

The role played by the finite shifts for ibT is played by the unboundedcomputable shifts for cl:

Af = {f (x) : x ∈ A}

where f is computable, strictly increasing, and f (n)− n→∞:Af <cl A.

In contrast to the finite shifts A + k which are discrete and invertible,the unbounded computable shifts are dense and, in general, notinvertible.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 25 / 29

(RibT,≤) vs. (Rcl,≤): Finite Shifts and Cupping

The observation that, for any noncomputable set A, A + 1 <ibT Acan be strengthened as follows.

FINITE-SHIFT LEMMA (AS; special case). Let A and B be c.e. setssuch that A + 1 ∩ B = ∅ and A ≤ibT A + 1 ∪ B. Then A ≤ibT B.

DEFINITION. Let (P,≤) be a partial ordering and let a ∈ P. Anelement b ≤ a of P is a-cuppable if a = b ∨ c for some c < a; and bis a-noncuppable.

The Finite-Shift Lemma implies

THEOREM (AS). Let a > 0 be a c.e. ibT-degree. Then any degreeb ≤ a such that b 6≤ a + 1 is a-cuppable.

In other words, there is a degree c < a (namely c = a + 1) such that

∀ b ∈ NCUP(a) (b ≤ c)

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 26 / 29

(RibT,≤) vs. (Rcl,≤): Cupping in the cl-Degrees

For the c.e. ibT-degrees we have observed: For any a > 0 there is adegree c < a (namely c = a + 1) such that ∀ b ∈ NCUP(a) (b ≤ c).

For the cl-degrees the corresponding fact fails:

THEOREM (AS, Bodewig, Fan, Kraling). There is a c.e. cl-degreea > 0 such that, for any c < a there is a a-noncuppable degree b < asuch that b 6≤ c.

COROLLARY. Th(RibT,≤) 6= Th(Rcl,≤).In fact, Σ5 − Th(RibT,≤) 6= Σ5 − Th(Rcl,≤).

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 27 / 29

(RibT,≤) vs. (Rcl,≤): Open Problems

We have shown that

Σ5 − Th(RibT,≤) 6= Σ5 − Th(Rcl,≤).

On the other hand, as mentioned before,

Σ1 − Th(RibT,≤) = Σ1 − Th(Rcl,≤).

OPEN PROBLEM. Up to what level Σk do the theories of (RibT,≤)and (Rcl,≤) agree?

OPEN PROBLEM. Is the partial ordering of all (not necessarily c.e.)ibT-degrees elementarily equivalent to the partial ordering of allcl-degrees.

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 28 / 29

THANK YOU!

Klaus Ambos-Spies (Heidelberg) Strongly Bounded Turing Degrees Novosibirsk 2011 29 / 29